Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 The paradox  





2 Responses  





3 Alternative usage  





4 See also  





5 Notes  





6 References  





7 External links  














Mere addition paradox: Difference between revisions






Español
Français
Lietuvių
Português
Svenska
 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




Print/export  







In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
 
















Appearance
   

 





Help
 

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Browse history interactively
 Previous editNext edit 
Content deleted Content added
Plutoplato (talk | contribs)
40 edits
Added to the first paragraph
Cubefox (talk | contribs)
60 edits
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit
(18 intermediate revisions by 16 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:

{{short description|Problem in ethics}}

{{tone|date=September 2016}}

{{tone|date=September 2016}}

{{Utilitarianism |expanded=Problems}}

{{Utilitarianism |expanded=Problems}}



The '''mere addition paradox''', also known as the '''repugnant conclusion''', is a problem in [[ethics]], identified by [[Derek Parfit]] and discussed in his book ''[[Reasons and Persons]]'' (1984). The paradox identifies the mutual incompatibility of four intuitively compelling assertions about the relative value of populations. Parfit’s original formulation of the repugnant conclusion is that, “For any perfectly equal Population with very high positive welfare, there is a population with very low positive welfare which is better, other things being equal.”<ref>[[Derek Parfit]], Reasons and Persons ([[Clarendon Press]], 1984), p. 388.</ref>

The '''mere addition paradox''' (also known as the '''repugnant conclusion''') is a problem in [[ethics]] identified by [[Derek Parfit]] and discussed in his book ''[[Reasons and Persons]]'' (1984). The paradox identifies the mutual incompatibility of four intuitively compelling assertions about the relative value of populations. Parfit’s original formulation of the repugnant conclusion is that “For any perfectly equal population with very high positive welfare, there is a population with very low positive welfare which is better, other things being equal.”<ref>[[Derek Parfit]], Reasons and Persons ([[Clarendon Press]], 1984), p. 388.</ref>



==The paradox==

==The paradox==



Consider the four populations depicted in the following diagram: A, A+, B− and B. Each bar represents a distinct group of people, with the group's size represented by the bar's width and the [[happiness]] of each of the group's members represented by the bar's height. Unlike A and B, A+ and B− are complex populations, each comprising two distinct groups of people. It is also stipulated that the lives of the members of each group are good enough that it is better for them to be alive than for them to not exist.

Consider the four populations depicted in the following diagram: A, A+, B− and B. Each bar represents a distinct group of people. The bar's width represents group size while the bar's height represents group [[happiness]]. Unlike A and B, A+ and B− are complex populations, each comprising two distinct groups of people. It is also stipulated that the lives of the members of each group are good enough that they would rather be alive than not exist.



[[Image:MereAddition.svg|center]]

[[Image:MereAddition.svg|center]]



How do these populations compare in value? Parfit makes the following three suggestions:

Parfit makes the following three suggestions regarding the value of the populations:



::'''1.''' A+ seems no worse than A. This is because the people in A are no worse-off in A+, while the additional people who exist in A+ are better off in A+ compared to A, since it is stipulated that their lives are good enough that living them is better than not existing.

::'''1.''' A+ seems no worse than A. This is because the people in A are no worse-off in A+, while the additional people who exist in A+ are better off in A+ compared to A, since it is stipulated that their lives are good enough that it is better for them to be alive thanto not exist.



::'''2.''' B− seems better than A+. This is because B− has greater total and average happiness than A+.

::'''2.''' B− seems better than A+. This is because B− has greater total and average happiness than A+.

Line 22: Line 23:

::'''4.''' When we directly compare A (a population with high average happiness) and B (a population with lower average happiness, but more total happiness because of its larger population), it may seem that B can be worse than A.

::'''4.''' When we directly compare A (a population with high average happiness) and B (a population with lower average happiness, but more total happiness because of its larger population), it may seem that B can be worse than A.



Thus, there is a paradox. The following intuitively plausible claims are jointly incompatible: (1) that A+ is no worse than A, (2) that B− is better than A+, (3) that B− is equally as good as B, and (4) that B can be worse than A.

Thus, there is a paradox. The following intuitively plausible claims are jointly incompatible: (1) that A+ is no worse than A, (2) that B− is better than A+, (3) that B− is as good as B, and (4) that B can be worse than A.



==Responses==

==Criticisms and responses==

Some scholars, such as [[Larry Temkin]] and Stuart Rachels, argue that the apparent inconsistency between the four claims just outlined relies on the assumption that the "better than" relation is [[Transitive relation|transitive]]. We may resolve the inconsistency, thus, by rejecting the assumption. On this view, from the fact that A+ is no worse than A and that B− is better than A+ it simply does not follow that B− is better than A.

Some scholars, such as [[Larry Temkin]] and Stuart Rachels, argue that inconsistencies between the four claims (above) relies on the assumption that the "better than" relation is [[Transitive relation|transitive]]. The inconsistency could then be resolved by rejecting the assumption. According to this view, although A+ is no worse than A, and B− is better than A+, it does not follow that B− is better than A.



[[Torbjörn Tännsjö]] argues that the intuition that B is worse than A is wrong. While the lives of those in B are worse than those in A, there are more of them and thus the collective value of B is greater than A.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Torbjörn|first=Tännsjö|date=November 2002|title=Why We Ought to Accept the Repugnant Conclusion|journal=Utilitas|volume=14|issue=3|pages=339–359|doi=10.1017/S0953820800003642}}</ref> [[Michael Huemer]] also argues that the repugnant conclusion is not repugnant and that normal intuition is wrong.<ref name="huemer">{{cite journal| url=https://stripe.colorado.edu/~boonind/Huemer%20-%20In%20Defence%20of%20Repugnance.pdf| title=InDefenceofRepugnance| first=Michael| last=Huemer }}</ref>

[[Torbjörn Tännsjö]] argues that the intuition that B is worse than A is wrong. While the lives of those in B are worse than those in A, there are more of them, and thus the collective value of B is greater than A.<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Torbjörn|first=Tännsjö|date=November 2002|title=Why We Ought to Accept the Repugnant Conclusion|journal=Utilitas|volume=14|issue=3|pages=339–359|doi=10.1017/S0953820800003642|s2cid=233360601 }}</ref> [[Michael Huemer]] also argues that the repugnant conclusion is not repugnant.<ref> Huemer, M. (2008), "Indefenceofrepugnance" Mind, 117, 899-933. </ref>



However, Parfit argues that the above discussion fails to appreciate the true source of repugnance. He claims that on the face of it, it may not be absurd to think that B is better than A. Suppose, then, that Bisin fact better than A, as Huemer argues. It follows that this revised intuition must hold in subsequent iterations of the original steps. For example, the next iteration would add even more people to B+, and then take the average of the total happiness, resulting in C-. If these steps are repeated over and over, the eventual result will be Z, a massive population with the minimum level of average happiness; this would be a population in which every member is leading a life barely worth living. Parfit claims that it is Z that is the repugnant conclusion.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Reasons and Persons|last=Parfit|first=Derek|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=1984|isbn=978-0198249085|location=New York|pages=|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/reasonspersons00parf}}</ref>

However, Parfit argues that the above discussion fails to appreciate the true source of repugnance. He claims that initially, it may not be wrong to think that B is better than A. Assuming thisistrue, as Huemer argues, it follows that this revised intuition must hold in subsequent iterations of the original steps. For example, the next iteration would add even more people to B+, and then take the average of the total happiness, resulting in C−. If these steps are repeated over and over, the eventual result will be Z, a massive population with the minimum level of average happiness; this would be a population in which every member is leading a life barely worth living. Parfit claims that it is Z that is the repugnant conclusion.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Reasons and Persons|last=Parfit|first=Derek|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=1984|isbn=978-0198249085|location=New York|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/reasonspersons00parf}}</ref>



==Alternative usage==

==Alternative usage==

Line 37: Line 38:


==See also==

==See also==

*''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' by [[John Rawls]]

*''[[A Theory of Justice]]''

*[[Asymmetry (population ethics)]]

*[[Asymmetry (population ethics)]]

*[[Average and total utilitarianism]]

*[[Average and total utilitarianism]]

*[[Carrying capacity]] and [[ecological footprint]]

*[[Carrying capacity]]

*[[Ecological footprint]]

*[[Nonidentity problem]]

*[[Nonidentity problem]]

*[[Human overpopulation|Overpopulation]]

*[[Human overpopulation]]

*[[Person-affecting view]]

*[[Person-affecting view]]

*[[Sorites paradox]]

*[[Sorites paradox]]

*[[Utility monster]]

*[[Utility monster]]

*[[Industrial Revolution]]



==Notes==

==Notes==


Revision as of 11:51, 12 April 2024

The mere addition paradox (also known as the repugnant conclusion) is a problem in ethics identified by Derek Parfit and discussed in his book Reasons and Persons (1984). The paradox identifies the mutual incompatibility of four intuitively compelling assertions about the relative value of populations. Parfit’s original formulation of the repugnant conclusion is that “For any perfectly equal population with very high positive welfare, there is a population with very low positive welfare which is better, other things being equal.”[1]

The paradox

Consider the four populations depicted in the following diagram: A, A+, B− and B. Each bar represents a distinct group of people. The bar's width represents group size while the bar's height represents group happiness. Unlike A and B, A+ and B− are complex populations, each comprising two distinct groups of people. It is also stipulated that the lives of the members of each group are good enough that they would rather be alive than not exist.

Parfit makes the following three suggestions regarding the value of the populations:

1. A+ seems no worse than A. This is because the people in A are no worse-off in A+, while the additional people who exist in A+ are better off in A+ compared to A, since it is stipulated that their lives are good enough that it is better for them to be alive than to not exist.
2. B− seems better than A+. This is because B− has greater total and average happiness than A+.
3. B seems equally as good as B−, as the only difference between B− and B is that the two groups in B− are merged to form one group in B.

Together, these three comparisons entail that B is better than A. However, Parfit also observes the following:

4. When we directly compare A (a population with high average happiness) and B (a population with lower average happiness, but more total happiness because of its larger population), it may seem that B can be worse than A.

Thus, there is a paradox. The following intuitively plausible claims are jointly incompatible: (1) that A+ is no worse than A, (2) that B− is better than A+, (3) that B− is as good as B, and (4) that B can be worse than A.

Responses

Some scholars, such as Larry Temkin and Stuart Rachels, argue that inconsistencies between the four claims (above) relies on the assumption that the "better than" relation is transitive. The inconsistency could then be resolved by rejecting the assumption. According to this view, although A+ is no worse than A, and B− is better than A+, it does not follow that B− is better than A.

Torbjörn Tännsjö argues that the intuition that B is worse than A is wrong. While the lives of those in B are worse than those in A, there are more of them, and thus the collective value of B is greater than A.[2] Michael Huemer also argues that the repugnant conclusion is not repugnant.[3]

However, Parfit argues that the above discussion fails to appreciate the true source of repugnance. He claims that initially, it may not be wrong to think that B is better than A. Assuming this is true, as Huemer argues, it follows that this revised intuition must hold in subsequent iterations of the original steps. For example, the next iteration would add even more people to B+, and then take the average of the total happiness, resulting in C−. If these steps are repeated over and over, the eventual result will be Z, a massive population with the minimum level of average happiness; this would be a population in which every member is leading a life barely worth living. Parfit claims that it is Z that is the repugnant conclusion.[4]

Alternative usage

An alternative use of the term mere addition paradox was presented in a paper by Hassoun in 2010.[5] It identifies paradoxical reasoning that occurs when certain statistical measures are used to calculate results over a population. For example, if a group of 100 people together control $100 worth of resources, the average wealth per capita is $1. If a single rich person then arrives with 1 million dollars, then the total group of 101 people controls $1,000,100, making average wealth per capita $9,901, implying a drastic shift away from poverty even though nothing has changed for the original 100 people. Hassoun defines a no mere addition axiom to be used for judging such statistical measures: "merely adding a rich person to a population should not decrease poverty" (although acknowledging that in actual practice adding rich people to a population may provide some benefit to the whole population).

This same argument can be generalized to many cases where proportional statistics are used: for example, a video game sold on a download service may be considered a failure if less than 20% of those who download the game demo then purchase the game. Thus, if 10,000 people download the demo of a game and 2,000 buy it, the game is a borderline success; however, it would be rendered a failure by an extra 500 people downloading the demo and not buying, even though this "mere addition" changes nothing with regard to income or consumer satisfaction from the previous situation.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Clarendon Press, 1984), p. 388.
  • ^ Torbjörn, Tännsjö (November 2002). "Why We Ought to Accept the Repugnant Conclusion". Utilitas. 14 (3): 339–359. doi:10.1017/S0953820800003642. S2CID 233360601.
  • ^ Huemer, M. (2008), "In defence of repugnance" Mind, 117, 899-933.
  • ^ Parfit, Derek (1984). Reasons and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0198249085.
  • ^ Another Mere Addition Paradox? Some Reflections on Variable Population Poverty Measurement. UNU-WIDER. November 2010. ISBN 978-92-9230-358-7. Retrieved 31 March 2015.
  • References


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Mere_addition_paradox&oldid=1218553057"

    Categories: 
    Population ethics
    Thought experiments in ethics
    Philosophical paradoxes
    Utilitarianism
    1984 introductions
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Wikipedia articles with style issues from September 2016
    All articles with style issues
     



    This page was last edited on 12 April 2024, at 11:51 (UTC).

    This version of the page has been revised. Besides normal editing, the reason for revision may have been that this version contains factual inaccuracies, vandalism, or material not compatible with the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki