Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Equivalent definition  





2 Relations to other classes  





3 RE-complete  





4 co-RE-complete  





5 See also  





6 References  














RE (complexity)






Català
Español
فارسی

עברית

Português
Српски / srpski

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 

(Redirected from Co-RE)

Incomputability theory and computational complexity theory, RE (recursively enumerable) is the classofdecision problems for which a 'yes' answer can be verified by a Turing machine in a finite amount of time.[1] Informally, it means that if the answer to a problem instance is 'yes', then there is some procedure that takes finite time to determine this, and this procedure never falsely reports 'yes' when the true answer is 'no'. However, when the true answer is 'no', the procedure is not required to halt; it may go into an "infinite loop" for some 'no' cases. Such a procedure is sometimes called a semi-algorithm, to distinguish it from an algorithm, defined as a complete solution to a decision problem.[2]

Similarly, co-RE is the set of all languages that are complements of a language in RE. In a sense, co-RE contains languages of which membership can be disproved in a finite amount of time, but proving membership might take forever.

Equivalent definition[edit]

Equivalently, RE is the class of decision problems for which a Turing machine can list all the 'yes' instances, one by one (this is what 'enumerable' means). Each member of RE is a recursively enumerable set and therefore a Diophantine set.

To show this is equivalent, note that if there is a machine that enumerates all accepted inputs, another machine that takes in a string can run and accept if the string is enumerated. Conversely, if a machine accepts when an input is in a language, another machine can enumerate all strings in the language by interleaving simulations of on every input and outputting strings that are accepted (there is an order of execution that will eventually get to every execution step because there are countably many ordered pairs of inputs and steps).

Relations to other classes[edit]

The set of recursive languages (R) is a subset of both RE and co-RE.[3] In fact, it is the intersection of those two classes, because we can decide any problem for which there exists a recogniser and also a co-recogniser by simply interleaving them until one obtains a result. Therefore:

.

Conversely, the set of languages that are neither RE nor co-RE is known as NRNC. These are the set of languages for which neither membership nor non-membership can be proven in a finite amount of time, and contain all other languages that are not in either REorco-RE. That is:

.

Not only are these problems undecidable, but neither they nor their complement are recursively enumerable.

In January of 2020, a preprint announced a proof that RE was equivalent to the class MIP* (the class where a classical verifier interacts with multiple all-powerful quantum provers who share entanglement);[4] a revised, but not yet fully reviewed, proof was published in Communications of the ACM in November 2021. The proof implies that the Connes embedding problem and Tsirelson's problem are false.[5]

RE-complete[edit]

RE-complete is the set of decision problems that are complete for RE. In a sense, these are the "hardest" recursively enumerable problems. Generally, no constraint is placed on the reductions used except that they must be many-one reductions.

Examples of RE-complete problems:

  1. Halting problem: Whether a program given a finite input finishes running or will run forever.
  2. ByRice's Theorem, deciding membership in any nontrivial subset of the set of recursive functionsisRE-hard. It will be complete whenever the set is recursively enumerable.
  3. John Myhill (1955)[6] proved that all creative sets are RE-complete.
  4. The uniform word problem for groupsorsemigroups. (Indeed, the word problem for some individual groupsisRE-complete.)
  5. Deciding membership in a general unrestricted formal grammar. (Again, certain individual grammars have RE-complete membership problems.)
  6. The validity problem for first-order logic.
  7. Post correspondence problem: Given a list of pairs of strings, determine if there is a selection from these pairs (allowing repeats) such that the concatenation of the first items (of the pairs) is equal to the concatenation of the second items.
  8. Determining if a Diophantine equation has any integer solutions.

co-RE-complete[edit]

co-RE-complete is the set of decision problems that are complete for co-RE. In a sense, these are the complements of the hardest recursively enumerable problems.

Examples of co-RE-complete problems:

  1. The domino problem for Wang tiles.
  2. The satisfiability problem for first-order logic.

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  • ^ Korfhage, Robert R. (1966). Logic and Algorithms, With Applications to the Computer and Information Sciences. Wiley. p. 89. A method of solution will be called a semi-algorithm for [a problem] P on [a device] M if the solution to P (if one exists) appears after the performance of finitely many steps. A semi-algorithm will be called an algorithm if, in addition, whenever the problem has no solution the method enables the device to determine this after a finite number of steps and halts.
  • ^ Complexity Zoo: Class co-RE
  • ^ Ji, Zhengfeng; Natarajan, Anand; Vidick, Thomas; Wright, John; Yuen, Henry (2020). "MIP*=RE". arXiv:2001.04383 [quant-ph].
  • ^ Ji, Zhengfeng; Natarajan, Anand; Vidick, Thomas; Wright, John; Yuen, Henry (November 2021). "MIP* = RE". Communications of the ACM. 64 (11): 131–138. doi:10.1145/3485628. S2CID 210165045.
  • ^ Myhill, John (1955), "Creative sets", Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 1 (2): 97–108, doi:10.1002/malq.19550010205, MR 0071379.

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=RE_(complexity)&oldid=1228386513"

    Categories: 
    Complexity classes
    Undecidable problems
     



    This page was last edited on 10 June 2024, at 23:38 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki