Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Ordinal numbers  





2 Examples and counterexamples  



2.1  Natural numbers  





2.2  Integers  





2.3  Reals  







3 Equivalent formulations  





4 Order topology  





5 See also  





6 References  














Well-order






Čeština
Dansk
Deutsch
Eesti
Español
Esperanto
فارسی
Français

Bahasa Indonesia
Italiano
עברית
Magyar
Nederlands

Polski
Português
Română
Suomi
Svenska
Türkçe
Українська
Tiếng Vit

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 

(Redirected from Well-ordering)

Transitive binary relations
  • t
  • e
  • Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
    Total, Semiconnex Anti-
    reflexive
    Equivalence relation Green tickY Green tickY
    Preorder (Quasiorder) Green tickY
    Partial order Green tickY Green tickY
    Total preorder Green tickY Green tickY
    Total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Prewellordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Well-quasi-ordering Green tickY Green tickY
    Well-ordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Lattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Join-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Meet-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict partial order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict weak order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
    Definitions, for all and
    Green tickY indicates that the column's property is always true the row's term (at the very left), while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general (it might, or might not, hold). For example, that every equivalence relation is symmetric, but not necessarily antisymmetric, is indicated by Green tickY in the "Symmetric" column and in the "Antisymmetric" column, respectively.

    All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation betransitive: for all if and then
    A term's definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table.

    Inmathematics, a well-order (orwell-orderingorwell-order relation) on a set S is a total orderingonS with the property that every non-empty subsetofS has a least element in this ordering. The set S together with the ordering is then called a well-ordered set. In some academic articles and textbooks these terms are instead written as wellorder, wellordered, and wellorderingorwell order, well ordered, and well ordering.

    Every non-empty well-ordered set has a least element. Every element s of a well-ordered set, except a possible greatest element, has a unique successor (next element), namely the least element of the subset of all elements greater than s. There may be elements, besides the least element, that have no predecessor (see § Natural numbers below for an example). A well-ordered set S contains for every subset T with an upper boundaleast upper bound, namely the least element of the subset of all upper bounds of TinS.

    If ≤ is a non-strict well ordering, then < is a strict well ordering. A relation is a strict well ordering if and only if it is a well-founded strict total order. The distinction between strict and non-strict well orders is often ignored since they are easily interconvertible.

    Every well-ordered set is uniquely order isomorphic to a unique ordinal number, called the order type of the well-ordered set. The well-ordering theorem, which is equivalent to the axiom of choice, states that every set can be well ordered. If a set is well ordered (or even if it merely admits a well-founded relation), the proof technique of transfinite induction can be used to prove that a given statement is true for all elements of the set.

    The observation that the natural numbers are well ordered by the usual less-than relation is commonly called the well-ordering principle (for natural numbers).

    Ordinal numbers[edit]

    Every well-ordered set is uniquely order isomorphic to a unique ordinal number, called the order type of the well-ordered set. The position of each element within the ordered set is also given by an ordinal number. In the case of a finite set, the basic operation of counting, to find the ordinal number of a particular object, or to find the object with a particular ordinal number, corresponds to assigning ordinal numbers one by one to the objects. The size (number of elements, cardinal number) of a finite set is equal to the order type.[1] Counting in the everyday sense typically starts from one, so it assigns to each object the size of the initial segment with that object as last element. Note that these numbers are one more than the formal ordinal numbers according to the isomorphic order, because these are equal to the number of earlier objects (which corresponds to counting from zero). Thus for finite n, the expression "n-th element" of a well-ordered set requires context to know whether this counts from zero or one. In a notation "β-th element" where β can also be an infinite ordinal, it will typically count from zero.

    For an infinite set the order type determines the cardinality, but not conversely: well-ordered sets of a particular cardinality can have many different order types (see § Natural numbers, below, for an example). For a countably infinite set, the set of possible order types is uncountable.

    Examples and counterexamples[edit]

    Natural numbers[edit]

    The standard ordering ≤ of the natural numbers is a well ordering and has the additional property that every non-zero natural number has a unique predecessor.

    Another well ordering of the natural numbers is given by defining that all even numbers are less than all odd numbers, and the usual ordering applies within the evens and the odds:

    This is a well-ordered set of order type ω + ω. Every element has a successor (there is no largest element). Two elements lack a predecessor: 0 and 1.

    Integers[edit]

    Unlike the standard ordering ≤ of the natural numbers, the standard ordering ≤ of the integers is not a well ordering, since, for example, the set of negative integers does not contain a least element.

    The following binary relation R is an example of well ordering of the integers: x R y if and only if one of the following conditions holds:

    1. x = 0
    2. x is positive, and y is negative
    3. x and y are both positive, and xy
    4. x and y are both negative, and |x| ≤ |y|

    This relation R can be visualized as follows:

    R is isomorphic to the ordinal number ω + ω.

    Another relation for well ordering the integers is the following definition: if and only if

    This well order can be visualized as follows:

    This has the order type ω.

    Reals[edit]

    The standard ordering ≤ of any real interval is not a well ordering, since, for example, the open interval does not contain a least element. From the ZFC axioms of set theory (including the axiom of choice) one can show that there is a well order of the reals. Also Wacław Sierpiński proved that ZF + GCH (the generalized continuum hypothesis) imply the axiom of choice and hence a well order of the reals. Nonetheless, it is possible to show that the ZFC+GCH axioms alone are not sufficient to prove the existence of a definable (by a formula) well order of the reals.[2] However it is consistent with ZFC that a definable well ordering of the reals exists—for example, it is consistent with ZFC that V=L, and it follows from ZFC+V=L that a particular formula well orders the reals, or indeed any set.

    An uncountable subset of the real numbers with the standard ordering ≤ cannot be a well order: Suppose X is a subset of well ordered by . For each xinX, let s(x) be the successor of xin ordering on X (unless x is the last element of X). Let whose elements are nonempty and disjoint intervals. Each such interval contains at least one rational number, so there is an injective function from Ato There is an injection from XtoA (except possibly for a last element of X, which could be mapped to zero later). And it is well known that there is an injection from to the natural numbers (which could be chosen to avoid hitting zero). Thus there is an injection from X to the natural numbers, which means that X is countable. On the other hand, a countably infinite subset of the reals may or may not be a well order with the standard . For example,

    Examples of well orders:

    Equivalent formulations[edit]

    If a set is totally ordered, then the following are equivalent to each other:

    1. The set is well ordered. That is, every nonempty subset has a least element.
    2. Transfinite induction works for the entire ordered set.
    3. Every strictly decreasing sequence of elements of the set must terminate after only finitely many steps (assuming the axiom of dependent choice).
    4. Every subordering is isomorphic to an initial segment.

    Order topology[edit]

    Every well-ordered set can be made into a topological space by endowing it with the order topology.

    With respect to this topology there can be two kinds of elements:

    For subsets we can distinguish:

    A subset is cofinal in the whole set if and only if it is unbounded in the whole set or it has a maximum that is also maximum of the whole set.

    A well-ordered set as topological space is a first-countable space if and only if it has order type less than or equal to ω1 (omega-one), that is, if and only if the set is countable or has the smallest uncountable order type.

    See also[edit]

    References[edit]

    1. ^ Bonnet, Rémi; Finkel, Alain; Haddad, Serge; Rosa-Velardo, Fernando (2013). "Ordinal theory for expressiveness of well-structured transition systems". Information and Computation. 224: 1–22. doi:10.1016/j.ic.2012.11.003. MR 3016456.
  • ^ Feferman, S. (1964). "Some Applications of the Notions of Forcing and Generic Sets". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 56 (3): 325–345. doi:10.4064/fm-56-3-325-345.

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Well-order&oldid=1228215999"

    Categories: 
    Order theory
    Ordinal numbers
    Wellfoundedness
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
     



    This page was last edited on 10 June 2024, at 01:42 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki