The Project Gutenberg EBook of The Conditions Of Existence As Affecting
The Perpetuation Of Living Beings, by Thomas H. Huxley

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever.  You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org


Title: The Conditions Of Existence As Affecting The Perpetuation Of Living Beings
       Lecture V. (of V.), Lectures To Working Men, at the Museum
              of Practical Geology, 1863, On Darwin's work: "Origin of
              Species".

Author: Thomas H. Huxley

Release Date: January 4, 2009 [EBook #2925]
Last Updated: January 22, 2013

Language: English

Character set encoding: ASCII

*** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE CONDITIONS OF EXISTENCE ***




Produced by Amy E. Zelmer, and David Widger






 




THE CONDITIONS OF EXISTENCE AS 
AFFECTING THE PERPETUATION OF LIVING  BEINGS  




Lecture V. (of VI.), "Lectures To Working Men", at the Museum of Practical  Geology, 1863, On Darwin's work: "Origin of Species".





By Thomas H. Huxley  











IN the last Lecture I endeavoured to prove to you that, while, as a  general rule, organic beings tend to reproduce their kind, there is in  them, also, a constantly recurring tendency to varyto vary to a  greater or to a less extent. Such a variety, I pointed out to you, might  arise from causes which we do not understand; we therefore called it  spontaneous; and it might come into existence as a definite and marked  thing, without any gradations between itself and the form which preceded  it. I further pointed out, that such a variety having once arisen, might  be perpetuated to some extent, and indeed to a very marked extent, without  any direct interference, or without any exercise of that process which we  called selection. And then I stated further, that by such selection, when  exercised artificiallyif you took care to breed only from those  forms which presented the same peculiarities of any variety which had  arisen in this mannerthe variation might be perpetuated, as far as  we can see, indefinitely.  

The next question, and it is an important one for us, is this: Is there  any limit to the amount of variation from the primitive stock which can be  produced by this process of selective breeding? In considering this  question, it will be useful to class the characteristics, in respect of  which organic beings vary, under two heads: we may consider structural  characteristics, and we may consider physiological characteristics.  

In the first place, as regards structural characteristics, I endeavoured  to show you, by the skeletons which I had upon the table, and by reference  to a great many well-ascertained facts, that the different breeds of  Pigeons, the Carriers, Pouters, and Tumblers, might vary in any of their  internal and important structural characters to a very great degree; not  only might there be changes in the proportions of the skull, and the  characters of the feet and beaks, and so on; but that there might be an  absolute difference in the number of the vertebrae of the back, as in the  sacral vertebrae of the Pouter; and so great is the extent of the  variation in these and similar characters that I pointed out to you, by  reference to the skeletons and the diagrams, that these extreme varieties  may absolutely differ more from one another in their structural characters  than do what naturalists call distinct SPECIES of pigeons; that is to say,  that they differ so much in structure that there is a greater difference  between the Pouter and the Tumbler than there is between such wild and  distinct forms as the Rock Pigeon or the Ring Pigeon, or the Ring Pigeon  and the Stock Dove; and indeed the differences are of greater value than  this, for the structural differences between these domesticated pigeons  are such as would be admitted by a naturalist, supposing he knew nothing  at all about their origin, to entitle them to constitute even distinct  genera.  

As I have used this term SPECIES, and shall probably use it a good deal, I  had better perhaps devote a word or two to explaining what I mean by it.  

Animals and plants are divided into groups, which become gradually  smaller, beginning with a KINGDOM, which is divided into SUB-KINGDOMS;  then come the smaller divisions called PROVINCES; and so on from a  PROVINCE to a CLASS from a CLASS to an ORDER, from ORDERS to FAMILIES, and  from these to GENERA, until we come at length to the smallest groups of  animals which can be defined one from the other by constant characters,  which are not sexual; and these are what naturalists call SPECIES in  practice, whatever they may do in theory.  

If, in a state of nature, you find any two groups of living beings, which  are separated one from the other by some constantly-recurring  characteristic, I don't care how slight and trivial, so long as it is  defined and constant, and does not depend on sexual peculiarities, then  all naturalists agree in calling them two species; that is what is meant  by the use of the word speciesthat is to say, it is, for the  practical naturalist, a mere question of structural differences. 1

We have seen nowto repeat this point once more, and it is very  essential that we should rightly understand itwe have seen that  breeds, known to have been derived from a common stock by selection, may  be as different in their structure from the original stock as species may  be distinct from each other.  

But is the like true of the physiological characteristics of animals? Do  the physiological differences of varieties amount in degree to those  observed between forms which naturalists call distinct species? This is a  most important point for us to consider.  

As regards the great majority of physiological characteristics, there is  no doubt that they are capable of being developed, increased, and modified  by selection.  

There is no doubt that breeds may be made as different as species in many  physiological characters. I have already pointed out to you very briefly  the different habits of the breeds of Pigeons, all of which depend upon  their physiological peculiarities,as the peculiar habit of  tumbling, in the Tumblerthe peculiarities of flight, in the  "homing" birds,the strange habit of spreading out the tail, and  walking in a peculiar fashion, in the Fantail,and, lastly, the  habit of blowing out the gullet, so characteristic of the Pouter. These  are all due to physiological modifications, and in all these respects  these birds differ as much from each other as any two ordinary species do.  

So with Dogs in their habits and instincts. It is a physiological  peculiarity which leads the Greyhound to chase its prey by sight,that  enables the Beagle to track it by the scent,that impels the Terrier  to its rat-hunting propensity,and that leads the Retriever to its  habit of retrieving. These habits and instincts are all the results of  physiological differences and peculiarities, which have been developed  from a common stock, at least there is every reason to believe so. But it  is a most singular circumstance, that while you may run through almost the  whole series of physiological processes, without finding a check to your  argument, you come at last to a point where you do find a check, and that  is in the reproductive processes. For there is a most singular  circumstance in respect to natural speciesat least about some of  themand it would be sufficient for the purposes of this argument if  it were true of only one of them, but there is, in fact, a great number of  such casesand that is, that, similar as they may appear to be to  mere races or breeds, they present a marked peculiarity in the  reproductive process. If you breed from the male and female of the same  race, you of course have offspring of the like kind, and if you make the  offspring breed together, you obtain the same result, and if you breed  from these again, you will still have the same kind of offspring; there is  no check. But if you take members of two distinct species, however similar  they may be to each other and make them breed together, you will find a  check, with some modifications and exceptions, however, which I shall  speak of presently. If you cross two such species with each other, then,although  you may get offspring in the case of the first cross, yet, if you attempt  to breed from the products of that crossing, which are what are called  HYBRIDSthat is, if you couple a male and a female hybridthen  the result is that in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred you will get no  offspring at all; there will be no result whatsoever.  

The reason of this is quite obvious in some cases; the male hybrids,  although possessing all the external appearances and characteristics of  perfect animals, are physiologically imperfect and deficient in the  structural parts of the reproductive elements necessary to generation. It  is said to be invariably the case with the male mule, the cross between  the Ass and the Mare; and hence it is, that, although crossing the Horse  with the Ass is easy enough, and is constantly done, as far as I am aware,  if you take two mules, a male and a female, and endeavour to breed from  them, you get no offspring whatever; no generation will take place. This  is what is called the sterility of the hybrids between two distinct  species.  

You see that this is a very extraordinary circumstance; one does not see  why it should be. The common teleological explanation is, that it is to  prevent the impurity of the blood resulting from the crossing of one  species with another, but you see it does not in reality do anything of  the kind. There is nothing in this fact that hybrids cannot breed with  each other, to establish such a theory; there is nothing to prevent the  Horse breeding with the Ass, or the Ass with the Horse. So that this  explanation breaks down, as a great many explanations of this kind do,  that are only founded on mere assumptions.  

Thus you see that there is a great difference between "mongrels," which  are crosses between distinct races, and "hybrids," which are crosses  between distinct species. The mongrels are, so far as we know, fertile  with one another. But between species, in many cases, you cannot succeed  in obtaining even the first cross: at any rate it is quite certain that  the hybrids are often absolutely infertile one with another.  

Here is a feature, then, great or small as it may be, which distinguishes  natural species of animals. Can we find any approximation to this in the  different races known to be produced by selective breeding from a common  stock? Up to the present time the answer to that question is absolutely a  negative one. As far as we know at present, there is nothing approximating  to this check. In crossing the breeds between the Fantail and the Pouter,  the Carrier and the Tumbler, or any other variety or race you may nameso  far as we know at presentthere is no difficulty in breeding  together the mongrels. Take the Carrier and the Fantail, for instance, and  let them represent the Horse and the Ass in the case of distinct species;  then you have, as the result of their breeding, the Carrier-Fantail  mongrel,we will say the male and female mongrel,and, as far  as we know, these two when crossed would not be less fertile than the  original cross, or than Carrier with Carrier. Here, you see, is a  physiological contrast between the races produced by selective  modification and natural species. I shall inquire into the value of this  fact, and of some modifying circumstances by and by; for the present I  merely put it broadly before you.  

But while considering this question of the limitations of species, a word  must be said about what is called RECURRENCEthe tendency of races  which have been developed by selective breeding from varieties to return  to their primitive type. This is supposed by many to put an absolute limit  to the extent of selective and all other variations. People say,It is  all very well to talk about producing these different races, but you know  very well that if you turned all these birds wild, these Pouters, and  Carriers, and so on, they would all return to their primitive stock.This  is very commonly assumed to be a fact, and it is an argument that is  commonly brought forward as conclusive; but if you will take the trouble  to inquire into it rather closely, I think you will find that it is not  worth very much. The first question of course is, Do they thus return to  the primitive stock? And commonly as the thing is assumed and accepted, it  is extremely difficult to get anything like good evidence of it. It is  constantly said, for example, that if domesticated Horses are turned wild,  as they have been in some parts of Asia Minor and South America, that they  return at once to the primitive stock from which they were bred. But the  first answer that you make to this assumption is, to ask who knows what  the primitive stock was; and the second answer is, that in that case the  wild Horses of Asia Minor ought to be exactly like the wild Horses of  South America. If they are both like the same thing, they ought manifestly  to be like each other! The best authorities, however, tell you that it is  quite different. The wild Horse of Asia is said to be of a dun colour,  with a largish head, and a great many other peculiarities; while the best  authorities on the wild Horses of South America tell you that there is no  similarity between their wild Horses and those of Asia Minor; the cut of  their heads is very different, and they are commonly chestnut or  bay-coloured. It is quite clear, therefore, that as by these facts there  ought to have been two primitive stocks, they go for nothing in support of  the assumption that races recur to one primitive stock, and so far as this  evidence is concerned, it falls to the ground.  

Suppose for a moment that it were so, and that domesticated races, when  turned wild, did return to some common condition, I cannot see that this  would prove much more than that similar conditions are likely to produce  similar results; and that when you take back domesticated animals into  what we call natural conditions, you do exactly the same thing as if you  carefully undid all the work you had gone through, for the purpose of  bringing the animal from its wild to its domesticated state. I do not see  anything very wonderful in the fact, if it took all that trouble to get it  from a wild state, that it should go back into its original state as soon  as you removed the conditions which produced the variation to the  domesticated form. There is an important fact, however, forcibly brought  forward by Mr. Darwin, which has been noticed in connection with the  breeding of domesticated pigeons; and it is, that however different these  breeds of pigeons may be from each other, and we have already noticed the  great differences in these breeds, that if, among any of those variations,  you chance to have a blue pigeon turn up, it will be sure to have the  black bars across the wings, which are characteristic of the original wild  stock, the Rock Pigeon.  

Now, this is certainly a very remarkable circumstance; but I do not see  myself how it tells very strongly either one way or the other. I think, in  fact, that this argument in favour of recurrence to the primitive type  might prove a great deal too much for those who so constantly bring it  forward. For example, Mr. Darwin has very forcibly urged, that nothing is  commoner than if you examine a dun horseand I had an opportunity of  verifying this illustration lately, while in the islands of the West  Highlands, where there are a great many dun horsesto find that  horse exhibit a long black stripe down his back, very often stripes on his  shoulder, and very often stripes on his legs. I, myself, saw a pony of  this description a short time ago, in a baker's cart, near Rothesay, in  Bute: it had the long stripe down the back, and stripes on the shoulders  and legs, just like those of the Ass, the Quagga, and the Zebra. Now, if  we interpret the theory of recurrence as applied to this case, might it  not be said that here was a case of a variation exhibiting the characters  and conditions of an animal occupying something like an intermediate  position between the Horse, the Ass, the Quagga, and the Zebra, and from  which these had been developed? In the same way with regard even to Man.  Every anatomist will tell you that there is nothing commoner, in  dissecting the human body, than to meet with what are called muscular  variationsthat is, if you dissect two bodies very carefully, you  will probably find that the modes of attachment and insertion of the  muscles are not exactly the same in both, there being great peculiarities  in the mode in which the muscles are arranged; and it is very singular,  that in some dissections of the human body you will come upon arrangements  of the muscles very similar indeed to the same parts in the Apes. Is the  conclusion in that case to be, that this is like the black bars in the  case of the Pigeon, and that it indicates a recurrence to the primitive  type from which the animals have been probably developed? Truly, I think  that the opponents of modification and variation had better leave the  argument of recurrence alone, or it may prove altogether too strong for  them.  

To sum up,the evidence as far as we have gone is against the  argument as to any limit to divergences, so far as structure is concerned;  and in favour of a physiological limitation. By selective breeding we can  produce structural divergences as great as those of species, but we cannot  produce equal physiological divergences. For the present I leave the  question there.  

Now, the next problem that lies before usand it is an extremely  important oneis this: Does this selective breeding occur in nature?  Because, if there is no proof of it, all that I have been telling you goes  for nothing in accounting for the origin of species. Are natural causes  competent to play the part of selection in perpetuating varieties? Here we  labour under very great difficulties. In the last lecture I had occasion  to point out to you the extreme difficulty of obtaining evidence even of  the first origin of those varieties which we know to have occurred in  domesticated animals. I told you, that almost always the origin of these  varieties is overlooked, so that I could only produce two of three cases,  as that of Gratio Kelleia and of the Ancon sheep. People forget, or do not  take notice of them until they come to have a prominence; and if that is  true of artificial cases, under our own eyes, and in animals in our own  care, how much more difficult it must be to have at first hand good  evidence of the origin of varieties in nature! Indeed, I do not know that  it is possible by direct evidence to prove the origin of a variety in  nature, or to prove selective breeding; but I will tell you what we can  proveand this comes to the same thingthat varieties exist in  nature within the limits of species, and, what is more, that when a  variety has come into existence in nature, there are natural causes and  conditions, which are amply competent to play the part of a selective  breeder; and although that is not quite the evidence that one would like  to havethough it is not direct testimonyyet it is exceeding  good and exceedingly powerful evidence in its way.  

As to the first point, of varieties existing among natural species, I  might appeal to the universal experience of every naturalist, and of any  person who has ever turned any attention at all to the characteristics of  plants and animals in a state of nature; but I may as well take a few  definite cases, and I will begin with Man himself.  

I am one of those who believe that, at present, there is no evidence  whatever for saying, that mankind sprang originally from any more than a  single pair; I must say, that I cannot see any good ground whatever, or  even any tenable sort of evidence, for believing that there is more than  one species of Man. Nevertheless, as you know, just as there are numbers  of varieties in animals, so there are remarkable varieties of men. I speak  not merely of those broad and distinct variations which you see at a  glance. Everybody, of course, knows the difference between a Negro and a  white man, and can tell a Chinaman from an Englishman. They each have  peculiar characteristics of colour and physiognomy; but you must recollect  that the characters of these races go very far deeperthey extend to  the bony structure, and to the characters of that most important of all  organs to usthe brain; so that, among men belonging to different  races, or even within the same race, one man shall have a brain a third,  or half, or even seventy per cent. bigger than another; and if you take  the whole range of human brains, you will find a variation in some cases  of a hundred per cent. Apart from these variations in the size of the  brain, the characters of the skull vary. Thus if I draw the figures of a  Mongul and of a Negro head on the blackboard, in the case of the last the  breadth would be about seven-tenths, and in the other it would be  nine-tenths of the total length. So that you see there is abundant  evidence of variation among men in their natural condition. And if you  turn to other animals there is just the same thing. The fox, for example,  which has a very large geographical distribution all over Europe, and  parts of Asia, and on the American Continent, varies greatly. There are  mostly large foxes in the North, and smaller ones in the South. In Germany  alone, the foresters reckon some eight different sorts.  

Of the tiger, no one supposes that there is more than one species; they  extend from the hottest parts of Bengal, into the dry, cold, bitter  steppes of Siberia, into a latitude of 50 degrees,so that they may  even prey upon the reindeer. These tigers have exceedingly different  characteristics, but still they all keep their general features, so that  there is no doubt as to their being tigers. The Siberian tiger has a thick  fur, a small mane, and a longitudinal stripe down the back, while the  tigers of Java and Sumatra differ in many important respects from the  tigers of Northern Asia. So lions vary; so birds vary; and so, if you go  further back and lower down in creation, you find that fishes vary. In  different streams, in the same country even, you will find the trout to be  quite different to each other and easily recognisable by those who fish in  the particular streams. There is the same differences in leeches; leech  collectors can easily point out to you the differences and the  peculiarities which you yourself would probably pass by; so with  fresh-water mussels; so, in fact, with every animal you can mention.  

In plants there is the same kind of variation. Take such a case even as  the common bramble. The botanists are all at war about it; some of them  wanting to make out that there are many species of it, and others  maintaining that they are but many varieties of one species; and they  cannot settle to this day which is a species and which is a variety!  

So that there can be no doubt whatsoever that any plant and any animal may  vary in nature; that varieties may arise in the way I have described,as  spontaneous varieties,and that those varieties may be perpetuated  in the same way that I have shown you spontaneous varieties are  perpetuated; I say, therefore, that there can be no doubt as to the origin  and perpetuation of varieties in nature.  

But the question now is:Does selection take place in nature? is  there anything like the operation of man in exercising selective breeding,  taking place in nature? You will observe that, at present, I say nothing  about species; I wish to confine myself to the consideration of the  production of those natural races which everybody admits to exist. The  question is, whether in nature there are causes competent to produce  races, just in the same way as man is able to produce by selection, such  races of animals as we have already noticed.  

When a variety has arisen, the CONDITIONS OF EXISTENCE are such as to  exercise an influence which is exactly comparable to that of artificial  selection. By Conditions of Existence I mean two things,there are  conditions which are furnished by the physical, the inorganic world, and  there are conditions of existence which are furnished by the organic  world. There is, in the first place, CLIMATE; under that head I include  only temperature and the varied amount of moisture of particular places.  In the next place there is what is technically called STATION, which meansgiven  the climate, the particular kind of place in which an animal or a plant  lives or grows; for example, the station of a fish is in the water, of a  fresh-water fish in fresh water; the station of a marine fish is in the  sea, and a marine animal may have a station higher or deeper. So again  with land animals: the differences in their stations are those of  different soils and neighbourhoods; some being best adapted to a  calcareous, and others to an arenaceous soil. The third condition of  existence is FOOD, by which I mean food in the broadest sense, the supply  of the materials necessary to the existence of an organic being; in the  case of a plant the inorganic matters, such as carbonic acid, water,  ammonia, and the earthy salts or salines; in the case of the animal the  inorganic and organic matters, which we have seen they require; then these  are all, at least the two first, what we may call the inorganic or  physical conditions of existence. Food takes a mid-place, and then come  the organic conditions; by which I mean the conditions which depend upon  the state of the rest of the organic creation, upon the number and kind of  living beings, with which an animal is surrounded. You may class these  under two heads: there are organic beings, which operate as 'opponents',  and there are organic beings which operate as 'helpers' to any given  organic creature. The opponents may be of two kinds: there are the  'indirect opponents', which are what we may call 'rivals'; and there are  the 'direct opponents', those which strive to destroy the creature; and  these we call 'enemies'. By rivals I mean, of course, in the case of  plants, those which require for their support the same kind of soil and  station, and, among animals, those which require the same kind of station,  or food, or climate; those are the indirect opponents; the direct  opponents are, of course, those which prey upon an animal or vegetable.  The 'helpers' may also be regarded as direct and indirect: in the case of  a carnivorous animal, for example, a particular herbaceous plant may in  multiplying be an indirect helper, by enabling the herbivora on which the  carnivore preys to get more food, and thus to nourish the carnivore more  abundantly; the direct helper may be best illustrated by reference to some  parasitic creature, such as the tape-worm. The tape-worm exists in the  human intestines, so that the fewer there are of men the fewer there will  be of tape-worms, other things being alike. It is a humiliating  reflection, perhaps, that we may be classed as direct helpers to the  tape-worm, but the fact is so: we can all see that if there were no men  there would be no tape-worms.  

It is extremely difficult to estimate, in a proper way, the importance and  the working of the Conditions of Existence. I do not think there were any  of us who had the remotest notion of properly estimating them until the  publication of Mr. Darwin's work, which has placed them before us with  remarkable clearness; and I must endeavour, as far as I can in my own  fashion, to give you some notion of how they work. We shall find it  easiest to take a simple case, and one as free as possible from every kind  of complication.  

I will suppose, therefore, that all the habitable part of this globethe  dry land, amounting to about 51,000,000 square miles,I will suppose  that the whole of that dry land has the same climate, and that it is  composed of the same kind of rock or soil, so that there will be the same  station everywhere; we thus get rid of the peculiar influence of different  climates and stations. I will then imagine that there shall be but one  organic being in the world, and that shall be a plant. In this we start  fair. Its food is to be carbonic acid, water and ammonia, and the saline  matters in the soil, which are, by the supposition, everywhere alike. We  take one single plant, with no opponents, no helpers, and no rivals; it is  to be a "fair field, and no favour". Now, I will ask you to imagine  further that it shall be a plant which shall produce every year fifty  seeds, which is a very moderate number for a plant to produce; and that,  by the action of the winds and currents, these seeds shall be equally and  gradually distributed over the whole surface of the land. I want you now  to trace out what will occur, and you will observe that I am not talking  fallaciously any more than a mathematician does when he expounds his  problem. If you show that the conditions of your problem are such as may  actually occur in nature and do not transgress any of the known laws of  nature in working out your proposition, then you are as safe in the  conclusion you arrive at as is the mathematician in arriving at the  solution of his problem. In science, the only way of getting rid of the  complications with which a subject of this kind is environed, is to work  in this deductive method. What will be the result, then? I will suppose  that every plant requires one square foot of ground to live upon; and the  result will be that, in the course of nine years, the plant will have  occupied every single available spot in the whole globe! I have chalked  upon the blackboard the figures by which I arrive at the result:  




calc (45K)





You will see from this that, at the end of the first year the single plant  will have produced fifty more of its kind; by the end of the second year  these will have increased to 2,500; and so on, in succeeding years, you  get beyond even trillions; and I am not at all sure that I could tell you  what the proper arithmetical denomination of the total number really is;  but, at any rate, you will understand the meaning of all those noughts.  Then you see that, at the bottom, I have taken the 51,000,000 of square  miles, constituting the surface of the dry land; and as the number of  square feet are placed under and subtracted from the number of seeds that  would be produced in the ninth year, you can see at once that there would  be an immense number more of plants than there would be square feet of  ground for their accommodation. This is certainly quite enough to prove my  point; that between the eighth and ninth year after being planted the  single plant would have stocked the whole available surface of the earth.  

This is a thing which is hardly conceivableit seems hardly  imaginableyet it is so. It is indeed simply the law of Malthus  exemplified. Mr. Malthus was a clergyman, who worked out this subject most  minutely and truthfully some years ago; he showed quite clearly,and  although he was much abused for his conclusions at the time, they have  never yet been disproved and never will behe showed that in  consequence of the increase in the number of organic beings in a  geometrical ratio, while the means of existence cannot be made to increase  in the same ratio, that there must come a time when the number of organic  beings will be in excess of the power of production of nutriment, and that  thus some check must arise to the further increase of those organic  beings. At the end of the ninth year we have seen that each plant would  not be able to get its full square foot of ground, and at the end of  another year it would have to share that space with fifty others the  produce of the seeds which it would give off.  

What, then, takes place? Every plant grows up, flourishes, occupies its  square foot of ground, and gives off its fifty seeds; but notice this,  that out of this number only one can come to anything; there is thus, as  it were, forty-nine chances to one against its growing up; it depends upon  the most fortuitous circumstances whether any one of these fifty seeds  shall grow up and flourish, or whether it shall die and perish. This is  what Mr. Darwin has drawn attention to, and called the "STRUGGLE FOR  EXISTENCE"; and I have taken this simple case of a plant because some  people imagine that the phrase seems to imply a sort of fight.  

I have taken this plant and shown you that this is the result of the ratio  of the increase, the necessary result of the arrival of a time coming for  every species when exactly as many members must be destroyed as are born;  that is the inevitable ultimate result of the rate of production. Now,  what is the result of all this? I have said that there are forty-nine  struggling against every one; and it amounts to this, that the smallest  possible start given to any one seed may give it an advantage which will  enable it to get ahead of all the others; anything that will enable any  one of these seeds to germinate six hours before any of the others will,  other things being alike, enable it to choke them out altogether. I have  shown you that there is no particular in which plants will not vary from  each other; it is quite possible that one of our imaginary plants may vary  in such a character as the thickness of the integument of its seeds; it  might happen that one of the plants might produce seeds having a thinner  integument, and that would enable the seeds of that plant to germinate a  little quicker than those of any of the others, and those seeds would most  inevitably extinguish the forty-nine times as many that were struggling  with them.  

I have put it in this way, but you see the practical result of the process  is the same as if some person had nurtured the one and destroyed the other  seeds. It does not matter how the variation is produced, so long as it is  once allowed to occur. The variation in the plant once fairly started  tends to become hereditary and reproduce itself; the seeds would spread  themselves in the same way and take part in the struggle with the  forty-nine hundred, or forty-nine thousand, with which they might be  exposed. Thus, by degrees, this variety, with some slight organic change  or modification, must spread itself over the whole surface of the  habitable globe, and extirpate or replace the other kinds. That is what is  meant by NATURAL SELECTION; that is the kind of argument by which it is  perfectly demonstrable that the conditions of existence may play exactly  the same part for natural varieties as man does for domesticated  varieties. No one doubts at all that particular circumstances may be more  favourable for one plant and less so for another, and the moment you admit  that, you admit the selective power of nature. Now, although I have been  putting a hypothetical case, you must not suppose that I have been  reasoning hypothetically. There are plenty of direct experiments which  bear out what we may call the theory of natural selection; there is  extremely good authority for the statement that if you take the seed of  mixed varieties of wheat and sow it, collecting the seed next year and  sowing it again, at length you will find that out of all your varieties  only two or three have lived, or perhaps even only one. There were one or  two varieties which were best fitted to get on, and they have killed out  the other kinds in just the same way and with just the same certainty as  if you had taken the trouble to remove them. As I have already said, the  operation of nature is exactly the same as the artificial operation of  man.  

But if this be true of that simple case, which I put before you, where  there is nothing but the rivalry of one member of a species with others,  what must be the operation of selective conditions, when you recollect as  a matter of fact, that for every species of animal or plant there are  fifty or a hundred species which might all, more or less, be comprehended  in the same climate, food, and station;that every plant has  multitudinous animals which prey upon it, and which are its direct  opponents; and that these have other animals preying upon them,that  every plant has its indirect helpers in the birds that scatter abroad its  seed, and the animals that manure it with their dung;I say, when  these things are considered, it seems impossible that any variation which  may arise in a species in nature should not tend in some way or other  either to be a little better or worse than the previous stock; if it is a  little better it will have an advantage over and tend to extirpate the  latter in this crush and struggle; and if it is a little worse it will  itself be extirpated.  

I know nothing that more appropriately expresses this, than the phrase,  "the struggle for existence"; because it brings before your minds, in a  vivid sort of way, some of the simplest possible circumstances connected  with it. When a struggle is intense there must be some who are sure to be  trodden down, crushed, and overpowered by others; and there will be some  who just manage to get through only by the help of the slightest accident.  I recollect reading an account of the famous retreat of the French troops,  under Napoleon, from Moscow. Worn out, tired, and dejected, they at length  came to a great river over which there was but one bridge for the passage  of the vast army. Disorganised and demoralised as that army was, the  struggle must certainly have been a terrible oneevery one heeding  only himself, and crushing through the ranks and treading down his  fellows. The writer of the narrative, who was himself one of those who  were fortunate enough to succeed in getting over, and not among the  thousands who were left behind or forced into the river, ascribed his  escape to the fact that he saw striding onward through the mass a great  strong fellow,one of the French Cuirassiers, who had on a large  blue cloakand he had enough presence of mind to catch and retain a  hold of this strong man's cloak. He says,I caught hold of his cloak, and  although he swore at me and cut at and struck me by turns, and at last,  when he found he could not shake me off, fell to entreating me to leave go  or I should prevent him from escaping, besides not assisting myself, I  still kept tight hold of him, and would not quit my grasp until he had at  last dragged me through.Here you see was a case of selective savingif  we may so term itdepending for its success on the strength of the  cloth of the Cuirassier's cloak. It is the same in nature; every species  has its bridge of Beresina; it has to fight its way through and struggle  with other species; and when well nigh overpowered, it may be that the  smallest chance, something in its colour, perhapsthe minutest  circumstancewill turn the scale one way or the other.  

Suppose that by a variation of the black race it had produced the white  man at any timeyou know that the Negroes are said to believe this  to have been the case, and to imagine that Cain was the first white man,  and that we are his descendantssuppose that this had ever happened,  and that the first residence of this human being was on the West Coast of  Africa. There is no great structural difference between the white man and  the Negro, and yet there is something so singularly different in the  constitution of the two, that the malarias of that country, which do not  hurt the black at all, cut off and destroy the white. Then you see there  would have been a selective operation performed; if the white man had  risen in that way, he would have been selected out and removed by means of  the malaria. Now there really is a very curious case of selection of this  sort among pigs, and it is a case of selection of colour too. In the woods  of Florida there are a great many pigs, and it is a very curious thing  that they are all black, every one of them. Professor Wyman was there some  years ago, and on noticing no pigs but these black ones, he asked some of  the people how it was that they had no white pigs, and the reply was that  in the woods of Florida there was a root which they called the Paint Root,  and that if the white pigs were to eat any of it, it had the effect of  making their hoofs crack, and they died, but if the black pigs eat any of  it, it did not hurt them at all. Here was a very simple case of natural  selection. A skilful breeder could not more carefully develope the black  breed of pigs, and weed out all the white pigs, than the Paint Root does.  

To show you how remarkably indirect may be such natural selective agencies  as I have referred to, I will conclude by noticing a case mentioned by Mr.  Darwin, and which is certainly one of the most curious of its kind. It is  that of the Humble Bee. It has been noticed that there are a great many  more humble bees in the neighbourhood of towns, than out in the open  country; and the explanation of the matter is this: the humble bees build  nests, in which they store their honey and deposit the larvae and eggs.  The field mice are amazingly fond of the honey and larvae; therefore,  wherever there are plenty of field mice, as in the country, the humble  bees are kept down; but in the neighbourhood of towns, the number of cats  which prowl about the fields eat up the field mice, and of course the more  mice they eat up the less there are to prey upon the larvae of the beesthe  cats are therefore the INDIRECT HELPERS of the bees! 2Coming back a  step farther we may say that the old maids are also indirect friends of  the humble bees, and indirect enemies of the field mice, as they keep the  cats which eat up the latter! This is an illustration somewhat beneath the  dignity of the subject, perhaps, but it occurs to me in passing, and with  it I will conclude this lecture.  


1 (return)
 [ I lay stress here on the  'practical' signification of "Species." Whether a physiological test  between species exist or not, it is hardly ever applicable by the  practical naturalist.]  


2 (return)
 [ The humble bees, on the  other hand, are direct helpers of some plants, such as the heartsease and  red clover, which are fertilized by the visits of the bees; and they are  indirect helpers of the numerous insects which are more or less completely  supported by the heartsease and red clover.]  











End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of The Conditions Of Existence As
Affecting The Perpetuation Of Living Beings, by Thomas H. Huxley

*** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE CONDITIONS OF EXISTENCE ***

***** This file should be named 2925-h.htm or 2925-h.zip *****
This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
        http://www.gutenberg.org/2/9/2/2925/

Produced by Amy E. Zelmer, and David Widger


Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
will be renamed.

Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
(and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
permission and without paying copyright royalties.  Special rules,
set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark.  Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission.  If you
do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy.  You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research.  They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks.  Redistribution is
subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
redistribution.



*** START: FULL LICENSE ***

THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
http://gutenberg.org/license).


Section 1.  General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic works

1.A.  By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement.  If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B.  "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark.  It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement.  There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.  See
paragraph 1.C below.  There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.  See paragraph 1.E below.

1.C.  The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works.  Nearly all the individual works in the
collection are in the public domain in the United States.  If an
individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
are removed.  Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
the work.  You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.

1.D.  The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work.  Copyright laws in most countries are in
a constant state of change.  If you are outside the United States, check
the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
Gutenberg-tm work.  The Foundation makes no representations concerning
the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
States.

1.E.  Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1.  The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase『Project
Gutenberg』is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
copied or distributed:

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever.  You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org

1.E.2.  If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
or charges.  If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
1.E.9.

1.E.3.  If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
terms imposed by the copyright holder.  Additional terms will be linked
to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.

1.E.4.  Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.

1.E.5.  Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg-tm License.

1.E.6.  You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
word processing or hypertext form.  However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
"Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
form.  Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7.  Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8.  You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
that

- You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
     the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
     you already use to calculate your applicable taxes.  The fee is
     owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
     has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
     Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.  Royalty payments
     must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
     prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
     returns.  Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
     sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
     address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
     the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."

- You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
     you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
     does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
     License.  You must require such a user to return or
     destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
     and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
     Project Gutenberg-tm works.

- You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
     money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
     electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
     of receipt of the work.

- You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
     distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.

1.E.9.  If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark.  Contact the
Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1.  Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
collection.  Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
"Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
your equipment.

1.F.2.  LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the『Right
of Replacement or Refund』described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees.  YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3.  YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.

1.F.3.  LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from.  If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
your written explanation.  The person or entity that provided you with
the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
refund.  If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.  If the second copy
is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4.  Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5.  Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
the applicable state law.  The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6.  INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.


Section  2.  Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm

Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.  It exists
because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need, are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
remain freely available for generations to come.  In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.


Section 3.  Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation

The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service.  The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541.  Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
http://pglaf.org/fundraising.  Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.

The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
throughout numerous locations.  Its business office is located at
809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
business@pglaf.org.  Email contact links and up to date contact
information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
page at http://pglaf.org

For additional contact information:
     Dr. Gregory B. Newby
     Chief Executive and Director
     gbnewby@pglaf.org


Section 4.  Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation

Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment.  Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States.  Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements.  We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance.  To
SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
particular state visit http://pglaf.org

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States.  U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses.  Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate


Section 5.  General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.

Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
with anyone.  For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.


Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
unless a copyright notice is included.  Thus, we do not necessarily
keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.


Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:

     http://www.gutenberg.org

This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.