Home  

Random  

Nearby  



Log in  



Settings  



Donate  



About Wikipedia  

Disclaimers  



Wikipedia





Kantianism





Article  

Talk  



Language  

Watch  

Edit  





Kantianism (German: Kantianismus) is the philosophy of Immanuel Kant, a German philosopher born in Königsberg, Prussia (now Kaliningrad, Russia). The term KantianismorKantian is sometimes also used to describe contemporary positions in philosophy of mind, epistemology, and ethics.

Ethics

edit

Kantian ethicsisdeontological, revolving entirely around duty rather than emotions or end goals. All actions are performed in accordance with some underlying maxim or principle, which are vastly different from each other; it is according to this that the moral worth of any action is judged. Kant's ethics are founded on his view of rationality as the ultimate good and his belief that all people are fundamentally rational beings. This led to the most important part of Kant's ethics, the formulation of the categorical imperative, which is the criterion for whether a maxim is good or bad.

Simply put, this criterion amounts to a thought experiment: to attempt to universalize the maxim (by imagining a world where all people necessarily acted in this way in the relevant circumstances) and then see if the maxim and its associated action would still be conceivable in such a world. For instance, holding the maxim kill anyone who annoys you and applying it universally would result in self termination. Thus holding this maxim is irrational as it ends up being impossible to hold it.

Universalizing a maxim (statement) leads to it being valid, or to one of two contradictions—a contradiction in conception (where the maxim, when universalized, is no longer a viable means to the end) or a contradiction in will (where the will of a person contradicts what the universalisation of the maxim implies). The first type leads to a "perfect duty", and the second leads to an "imperfect duty".

Kant's ethics focus, then, only on the maxim that underlies actions, and judges these to be good or bad solely on how they conform to reason. Kant showed that many of our common sense views of what is good or bad conform to his system, but denied that any action performed for reasons other than rational actions can be good (saving someone who is drowning simply out of a great pity for them is not a morally good act). Kant also denied that the consequences of an act in any way contribute to the moral worth of that act—his reasoning being (highly simplified for brevity) that the physical world is outside our full control, and thus we cannot be held accountable for the events that occur in it.

The formulations of the categorical imperative:

  1. Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law.[1]
  2. Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never merely as a means to an end, but always at the same time as an end.[2]
  3. Therefore, every rational being must so act as if he were, through his maxim, always a legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends.[3]

Political philosophy

edit

Inpolitical philosophy, Kant has had wide and increasing influence with major political philosophers of the late twentieth century. For example, John Rawls[4][5] drew heavily on his inspiration in setting out the basis for a liberal view of political institutions.[clarification needed] The nature of Rawls' use of Kant has engendered serious controversy [clarification needed] but has demonstrated the vitality of Kantian considerations across a wider range of questions than was once thought plausible.

See also

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ Kant, Immanuel (1993). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by James W. Ellington (3rd ed.). Hackett. p. 30. ISBN 0-87220-166-X.
  • ^ Kant, Immanuel (1993). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by James W. Ellington (3rd ed.). Hackett. p. 36. ISBN 0-87220-166-X.
  • ^ Kant, Immanuel (1993). Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by James W. Ellington (3rd ed.). Hackett. p. 43. ISBN 0-87220-166-X.
  • ^ Thomas, Domjahn (4 May 2007). John Rawls and Immanuel Kant - A Comparison (seminar paper, 2006). ISBN 9783640089369. Retrieved 14 August 2019.
  • ^ Vadim, Chaly (June 2015). "An Interpretation of Rawls' "Kantian Interpretation"". CON-TEXTOS KANTIANOS. International Journal of Philosophy. 1 (1): 142–155. doi:10.5281/zenodo.18510. Retrieved 14 August 2019.
  • Bibliography

    edit
    edit

    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Kantianism&oldid=1192562380"
     



    Last edited on 30 December 2023, at 01:39  





    Languages

     


    العربية
    Azərbaycanca
    Български
    Deutsch
    Español
    فارسی

    Հայերեն
    ि
    Bahasa Indonesia
    עברית

    Polski
    Português
    Română
    Русский
    Shqip
    Slovenčina
    Suomi
    ி
    Türkçe
    Українська

     

    Wikipedia


    This page was last edited on 30 December 2023, at 01:39 (UTC).

    Content is available under CC BY-SA 4.0 unless otherwise noted.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Terms of Use

    Desktop