Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Definitions  



1.1  As a truth function  



1.1.1  Truth table  







1.2  As a formal connective  







2 Formal properties  





3 Philosophical problems with material conditional  





4 See also  



4.1  Conditionals  







5 References  





6 Further reading  





7 External links  














Material conditional







العربية
Беларуская
Беларуская (тарашкевіца)
Български
Català
Čeština
Deutsch
Eesti
Español
Esperanto
فارسی
Français
Հայերեն
Hrvatski
Italiano
עברית
Қазақша
Magyar
Македонски
Nederlands

Norsk bokmål
Piemontèis
Polski
Português
Qaraqalpaqsha
Română
Русский
Simple English
Slovenčina
Suomi
Svenska
Tagalog
Татарча / tatarça

Українська

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




Print/export  







In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
Wikifunctions
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Mulus2lus (talk | contribs)at17:54, 11 June 2018 (Truth table: changed color of false condition for better identification). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.
(diff)  Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision  (diff)

Venn diagram of the truth function of the material conditional . The circle on the left bounds all members of set , and the one on the right bounds all members of set . The red area describes all members for which the material conditional is true, and the white area describes all members for which it is false. The material conditional differs significantly from a natural language's "if...then..." statement. It is only false when both the antecedent is true and the consequent is false.

The material conditional (also known as material implication, material consequence, or simply implication, implies, or conditional) is a logical connective (or a binary operator) that is often symbolized by a forward arrow "→". The material conditional is used to form statements of the form p → q (termed a conditional statement) which is read as "if p then q". Unlike the English construction "if... then...", the material conditional statement p → q does not specify a causal relationship between p and q. It is merely to be understood to mean "if p is true, then q is also true" such that the statement p → q is false only when p is true and q is false.[1]  The material conditional only states that q is true when (but not necessarily only when) p is true, and makes no claim that p causes q.

The material conditional is also symbolized using:

  1. 𝑝 ⊃ 𝑞 (Although this symbol may be used for the superset symbol in set theory.);
  2. 𝑝 ⇒ 𝑞 (Although this symbol is often used for logical consequence (i.e., logical implication) rather than for material conditional.)
  3. C𝑝𝑞 (using Łukasiewicz notationorBocheński notation)

With respect to the material conditionals above:

Conditional statements may be nested such that either or both of the antecedent or the consequent may themselves be conditional statements. In the example "(pq) → (rs)", meaning "if the truth of p implies the truth of q, then the truth of r implies the truth of s), both the antecedent and the consequent are conditional statements.

Inclassical logic islogically equivalentto and by De Morgan's Law logically equivalent to .[2] Whereas, in minimal logic (and therefore also intuitionistic logic) only logically entails ; and in intuitionistic logic (but not minimal logic) entails .

Definitions

Logicians have many different views on the nature of material implication and approaches to explain its sense.[3]

As a truth function

Inclassical logic, the compound pq is logically equivalent to the negative compound: not both p and not q. Thus the compound pqisfalse if and only if both p is true and q is false. By the same stroke, pqistrue if and only if either p is false or q is true (or both). Thus → is a function from pairs of truth values of the components p, q to truth values of the compound pq, whose truth value is entirely a function of the truth values of the components. Hence, this interpretation is called truth-functional. The compound pq is logically equivalent also to ¬pq (either not p, or q (or both)), and to ¬q¬p (if not q then not p). But it is not equivalent to ¬p¬q, which is equivalent to qp.

Truth table

The truth table associated with the material conditional pq is identical to that of ¬pq. It is as follows:

T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T

It may also be useful to note that in Boolean algebra, true and false can be denoted as 1 and 0 respectively with an equivalent table.

As a formal connective

The material conditional can be considered as a symbol of a formal theory, taken as a set of sentences, satisfying all the classical inferences involving →, in particular the following characteristic rules:

  1. Modus ponens;
  2. Conditional proof;
  3. Classical contraposition;
  4. Classical reductio ad absurdum.

Unlike the truth-functional one, this approach to logical connectives permits the examination of structurally identical propositional forms in various logical systems, where somewhat different properties may be demonstrated. For example, in intuitionistic logic which rejects proofs by contraposition as valid rules of inference, (p → q) ⇒ ¬p ∨ q is not a propositional theorem, but the material conditional is used to define negation.

Formal properties

When studying logic formally, the material conditional is distinguished from the semantic consequence relation . We say if every interpretation that makes A true also makes B true. However, there is a close relationship between the two in most logics, including classical logic. For example, the following principles hold:

These principles do not hold in all logics, however. Obviously they do not hold in non-monotonic logics, nor do they hold in relevance logics.

Other properties of implication (the following expressions are always true, for any logical values of variables):

Note that islogically equivalentto; this property is sometimes called un/currying. Because of these properties, it is convenient to adopt a right-associative notation for → where denotes .

Comparison of Boolean truth tables shows that is equivalent to , and one is an equivalent replacement for the other in classical logic. See material implication (rule of inference).

Philosophical problems with material conditional

Outside of mathematics, it is a matter of some controversy as to whether the truth function for material implication provides an adequate treatment of conditional statements in a natural language such as English, i.e., indicative conditionals and counterfactual conditionals. An indicative conditional is a sentence in the indicative mood with a conditional clause attached. A counterfactual conditional is a false-to-fact sentence in the subjunctive mood.[4] That is to say, critics argue that in some non-mathematical cases, the truth value of a compound statement, "if p then q", is not adequately determined by the truth values of p and q.[4] Examples of non-truth-functional statements include: "q because p", "p before q" and "it is possible that p".[4]

"[Of] the sixteen possible truth-functions of A and B, material implication is the only serious candidate. First, it is uncontroversial that when A is true and B is false, "If A, B" is false. A basic rule of inference is modus ponens: from "If A, B" and A, we can infer B. If it were possible to have A true, B false and "If A, B" true, this inference would be invalid. Second, it is uncontroversial that "If A, B" is sometimes true when A and B are respectively (true, true), or (false, true), or (false, false)… Non-truth-functional accounts agree that "If A, B" is false when A is true and B is false; and they agree that the conditional is sometimes true for the other three combinations of truth-values for the components; but they deny that the conditional is always true in each of these three cases. Some agree with the truth-functionalist that when A and B are both true, "If A, B" must be true. Some do not, demanding a further relation between the facts that A and that B."[4]

The truth-functional theory of the conditional was integral to Frege's new logic (1879). It was taken up enthusiastically by Russell (who called it "material implication"), Wittgenstein in the Tractatus, and the logical positivists, and it is now found in every logic text. It is the first theory of conditionals which students encounter. Typically, it does not strike students as obviously correct. It is logic's first surprise. Yet, as the textbooks testify, it does a creditable job in many circumstances. And it has many defenders. It is a strikingly simple theory: "If A, B" is false when A is true and B is false. In all other cases, "If A, B" is true. It is thus equivalent to "~(A&~B)" and to "~AorB". "AB" has, by stipulation, these truth conditions.

— Dorothy Edgington, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "Conditionals"[4]

The meaning of the material conditional can sometimes be used in the English "if condition then consequence" construction (a kind of conditional sentence), where condition and consequence are to be filled with English sentences. However, this construction also implies a "reasonable" connection between the condition (protasis) and consequence (apodosis) (see Connexive logic).[citation needed]

The material conditional can yield some unexpected truths when expressed in natural language. For example, any material conditional statement with a false antecedent is true (see vacuous truth). So the statement "if 2 is odd then 2 is even" is true. Similarly, any material conditional with a true consequent is true. So the statement "if I have a penny in my pocket then Paris is in France" is always true, regardless of whether or not there is a penny in my pocket. These problems are known as the paradoxes of material implication, though they are not really paradoxes in the strict sense; that is, they do not elicit logical contradictions. These unexpected truths arise because speakers of English (and other natural languages) are tempted to equivocate between the material conditional and the indicative conditional, or other conditional statements, like the counterfactual conditional and the material biconditional.

It is not surprising that a rigorously defined truth-functional operator does not correspond exactly to all notions of implication or otherwise expressed by 'if ... then ...' sentences in natural languages. For an overview of some of the various analyses, formal and informal, of conditionals, see the "References" section below. Relevance logic attempts to capture these alternate concepts of implication that material implication glosses over.

See also

Conditionals

References

  1. ^ Magnus, P.D (January 6, 2012). "forallx: An Introduction to Formal Logic" (PDF). Creative Commons. p. 25. Retrieved 28 May 2013.
  • ^ Teller, Paul (January 10, 1989). "A Modern Formal Logic Primer: Sentence Logic Volume 1" (PDF). Prentice Hall. p. 54. Retrieved 28 May 2013.
  • ^ Clarke, Matthew C. (March 1996). "A Comparison of Techniques for Introducing Material Implication". Cornell University. Retrieved March 4, 2012.
  • ^ a b c d e Edgington, Dorothy (2008). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Conditionals". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 ed.).
  • Further reading

    External links


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Material_conditional&oldid=845422048"

    Categories: 
    Logical connectives
    Conditionals
    Logical consequence
    Hidden categories: 
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from February 2012
    Pages that use a deprecated format of the math tags
     



    This page was last edited on 11 June 2018, at 17:54 (UTC).

    This version of the page has been revised. Besides normal editing, the reason for revision may have been that this version contains factual inaccuracies, vandalism, or material not compatible with the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki