Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Formal accounts  





2 A priori property of logical consequence  





3 Proofs and models  



3.1  Syntactic consequence  





3.2  Semantic consequence  







4 Modal accounts  



4.1  Modal-formal accounts  





4.2  Warrant-based accounts  





4.3  Non-monotonic logical consequence  







5 See also  





6 Notes  





7 Resources  





8 External links  














Logical consequence






العربية
Български
Català
Deutsch
Ελληνικά
Español
Esperanto
فارسی
Français

ि
Bahasa Indonesia
עברית
Nederlands

Polski
Português
Русский
Slovenščina
کوردی
Српски / srpski
Suomi
Svenska

Українська


 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental conceptinlogic which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically follows from one or more statements. A valid logical argument is one in which the conclusion is entailed by the premises, because the conclusion is the consequence of the premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves the questions: In what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises? and What does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?[1] All of philosophical logic is meant to provide accounts of the nature of logical consequence and the nature of logical truth.[2]

Logical consequence is necessary and formal, by way of examples that explain with formal proof and models of interpretation.[1] A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given language, if and only if, using only logic (i.e., without regard to any personal interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set is true.[3]

Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence regarding a given language , either by constructing a deductive system for or by formal intended semantics for language . The Polish logician Alfred Tarski identified three features of an adequate characterization of entailment: (1) The logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences: (2) The relation is a priori, i.e., it can be determined with or without regard to empirical evidence (sense experience); and (3) The logical consequence relation has a modal component.[3]

Formal accounts[edit]

The most widely prevailing view on how best to account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form.

Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as:

All X are Y
All Y are Z
Therefore, all X are Z.

This argument is formally valid, because every instance of arguments constructed using this scheme is valid.

This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son", not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true in all cases, however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "PisQ's brother's son, therefore PisQ's nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a formal argument.[1]

A priori property of logical consequence[edit]

If it is known that follows logically from , then no information about the possible interpretations of or will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that is a logical consequence of cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge.[1] Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori.[1] However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.[1]

Proofs and models[edit]

The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of proofs and via models. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) proof theory whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) model theory.[4]

Syntactic consequence[edit]

A formula is a syntactic consequence[5][6][7][8][9] within some formal system of a set of formulas if there is a formal proofinof from the set . This is denoted . The turnstile symbol was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934–1935). [9]

Syntactic consequence does not depend on any interpretation of the formal system.[10]

Semantic consequence[edit]

A formula is a semantic consequence within some formal system of a set of statements if and only if there is no model in which all members of are true and is false.[11] This is denoted . Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make true.

Modal accounts[edit]

Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea:

is true if and only if it is necessary that if all of the elements of are true, then is true.

Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently):

is true if and only if it is impossible for all of the elements of to be true and false.

Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a universal quantifier over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as:

is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of are true and is false (untrue).

Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above:

All frogs are green.
Kermit is a frog.
Therefore, Kermit is green.

The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can not imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.

Modal-formal accounts[edit]

Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea:

if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as / to have true premises and a false conclusion.

Warrant-based accounts[edit]

The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational", in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.

Non-monotonic logical consequence[edit]

The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if is a consequence of , then is a consequence of any superset of . It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of

{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird}

but not of

{Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird, Tweety is a penguin}.

See also[edit]

  • Ampheck
  • Boolean algebra (logic)
  • Boolean domain
  • Boolean function
  • Boolean logic
  • Causality
  • Deductive reasoning
  • Logic gate
  • Logical graph
  • Peirce's law
  • Probabilistic logic
  • Propositional calculus
  • Sole sufficient operator
  • Strict conditional
  • Tautology (logic)
  • Tautological consequence
  • Therefore sign
  • Turnstile (symbol)
  • Double turnstile
  • Validity
  • Notes[edit]

    1. ^ a b c d e f Beall, JC and Restall, Greg, Logical Consequence The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
  • ^ Quine, Willard Van Orman, Philosophy of Logic.
  • ^ a b McKeon, Matthew, Logical Consequence Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • ^ Kosta Dosen (1996). "Logical consequence: a turn in style". In Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara; Kees Doets; Daniele Mundici; Johan van Benthem (eds.). Logic and Scientific Methods: Volume One of the Tenth International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence, August 1995. Springer. p. 292. ISBN 978-0-7923-4383-7.
  • ^ Dummett, Michael (1993) philosophy of language Harvard University Press, p.82ff
  • ^ Lear, Jonathan (1986) and Logical Theory Cambridge University Press, 136p.
  • ^ Creath, Richard, and Friedman, Michael (2007) Cambridge companion to Carnap Cambridge University Press, 371p.
  • ^ FOLDOC: "syntactic consequence" Archived 2013-04-03 at the Wayback Machine
  • ^ a b S. C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics (1952), Van Nostrand Publishing. p.88.
  • ^ Hunter, Geoffrey, Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic, University of California Press, 1971, p. 75.
  • ^ Etchemendy, John, Logical consequence, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy
  • Resources[edit]

    External links[edit]


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Logical_consequence&oldid=1224059758"

    Categories: 
    Logical consequence
    Philosophical logic
    Metalogic
    Propositional calculus
    Semantic units
    Deductive reasoning
    Concepts in logic
    Syntax (logic)
    Binary operations
    Hidden categories: 
    Webarchive template wayback links
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Commons category link from Wikidata
    Articles with Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy links
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 16 May 2024, at 00:32 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki