Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Mohism and Legalism  





2 Confucius  





3 Xunzi  





4 Modern applications  





5 Notes  





6 Further reading  





7 External links  














Rectification of names: Difference between revisions







Русский

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




Print/export  



















Appearance
   

 





Help
 

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Browse history interactively
 Previous editNext edit 
Content deleted Content added
→‎Confucius: replace his with confucius's as it's the first mention in the section proper
→‎Confucius: -s for consistency
Line 22: Line 22:


== Confucius ==

== Confucius ==

The ''[[Analects]]'' states that social disorder often stems from failure to call things by their proper names, that is, to perceive, understand, and deal with [[reality]]. Confucius's solution to this was the "rectification of names". He gave an explanation to one of his disciples:

The ''[[Analects]]'' states that social disorder often stems from failure to call things by their proper names, that is, to perceive, understand, and deal with [[reality]]. Confucius' solution to this was the "rectification of names". He gave an explanation to one of his disciples:

{{Quotation|text=A superior man, in regard to what he does not know, shows a cautious reserve. If names be not correct, language is not in accordance with the truth of things. If language be not in accordance with the truth of things, affairs cannot be carried on to success. When affairs cannot be carried on to success, proprieties and music do not flourish. When proprieties and music do not flourish, punishments will not be properly awarded. When punishments are not properly awarded, the people do not know how to move hand or foot. Therefore a superior man considers it necessary that the names he uses may be spoken appropriately, and also that what he speaks may be carried out appropriately. What the superior man requires is just that in his words there may be nothing incorrect.|author=

{{Quotation|text=A superior man, in regard to what he does not know, shows a cautious reserve. If names be not correct, language is not in accordance with the truth of things. If language be not in accordance with the truth of things, affairs cannot be carried on to success. When affairs cannot be carried on to success, proprieties and music do not flourish. When proprieties and music do not flourish, punishments will not be properly awarded. When punishments are not properly awarded, the people do not know how to move hand or foot. Therefore a superior man considers it necessary that the names he uses may be spoken appropriately, and also that what he speaks may be carried out appropriately. What the superior man requires is just that in his words there may be nothing incorrect.|author=

[[Confucius]]|source=Analects, Book XIII, Chapter 3, verses 4–7, Analect 13.3, translated by [[James Legge]]<ref>{{cite book|title=Confucian analects: The great learning, and The doctrine of the mean|url=https://archive.org/details/confuciananalect00conf|url-access=registration|first=James|last=Legge|publisher=[[Dover Publications]]|year=1971|pages=[https://archive.org/details/confuciananalect00conf/page/263 263–264]|isbn=9780486227467 |author-link=James Legge}}</ref>}}

[[Confucius]]|source=Analects, Book XIII, Chapter 3, verses 4–7, Analect 13.3, translated by [[James Legge]]<ref>{{cite book|title=Confucian analects: The great learning, and The doctrine of the mean|url=https://archive.org/details/confuciananalect00conf|url-access=registration|first=James|last=Legge|publisher=[[Dover Publications]]|year=1971|pages=[https://archive.org/details/confuciananalect00conf/page/263 263–264]|isbn=9780486227467 |author-link=James Legge}}</ref>}}


Revision as of 07:19, 16 January 2023

The rectification of names (Chinese: ; pinyin: Zhèngmíng; Wade–Giles: Cheng-ming) is originally a doctrine of feudal Confucian designations and relationships, behaving accordingly to ensure social harmony.[1] Without such accordance society would essentially crumble and "undertakings would not be completed."[2] Mencius extended the doctrine to include questions of political legitimacy.[3]

When Confucius was asked what he would do if he was a governor, he said he would "rectify the names" to make words correspond to reality.

Mohism and Legalism

Because the rectification of names in the Analects of Confucius appears to have been written later, it arguably originates in Mozi (470–391 BC).[4] The scholarship of Herrlee G. Creel argued for its further development through "Legalist" Shen Buhai (400–337 BC) before the Confucian usage for the same reasons.[5] However, professor Zhenbin Sun considers Mozi's rectification consonant with the Confucian usage; Mozi considered it an important factor in the resolution of sociopolitical issues, and not simply legal affairs.[6]

The Mohist and "Legalistic" version of the rectification of names emphasizes the use of hermeneutics to find "objective models" ("fa", 法) for ethics and politics, as well as in practical fields of work, to order or govern society.[7] Mozi advocated language standards appropriate for use by ordinary people.[4] With minimal training, anyone could use these "objective, particularly operational or measurement-like standards"[8] to fix the referents of names, in particular giving identical names to equivalent social relationships and functions so as to apply identical standards of "correct" behavior in analogous situations.[9][10][11]

For Guan Zhong (who seemingly originated the Fa concept) as for the Mohists, Fa provided a system of objective, reliable, publicly accessible standards or models that individuals could use for themselves to decide their own actions,[12] in contrast to what Sinologist Chad Hansen terms the "cultivated intuition of self-admiration societies" whereby scholars steeped in old texts maintained a monopoly on moral decision-making. At the same time, Fa could also complement traditional schemes, and Guan Zhong himself uses it alongside the Confucian concept of ceremony (Li, 禮).[7] For the most part, Confucianism does not emphasize Fa, though the concept of norms that people can apply themselves is an older idea, and Han Confucians embraced Fa as an essential element of administration.[13][7]

Evolving out of the Mohists and school of logicians,[14] reformer Shen Buhai insisted that the ruler must be fully informed on the state of his realm, using Fa as administrative method to sort out informational categories or define functions ("names").[15] Shen Buhai and later Han Fei (280–233 BC) used this variation on the rectification of names for appointment, matching the words of the official, or his name/title/legal contract, with his performance.[5] Han Fei bases his propositions for lingual uniformity upon the development of this system,[4] proposing that functions could be strictly defined to prevent conflict and corruption, and objective rules (Fa) impervious to divergent interpretation could be established, judged solely by their effectiveness.[16]

By contrast, the Zhuangzi says that "great words are overflowing; small words haggling"(2.2), the true self lacks form(2.3), the mind can spontaneously select (2.4), asks whether language is different from the chirping of birds(2.5), and rejects assertion and denial(2.7), saying "to wear out one's spirit like powers contriving some view... without understanding that it is all the same is called 'three in the morning'".[17]

Confucius

The Analects states that social disorder often stems from failure to call things by their proper names, that is, to perceive, understand, and deal with reality. Confucius' solution to this was the "rectification of names". He gave an explanation to one of his disciples:

A superior man, in regard to what he does not know, shows a cautious reserve. If names be not correct, language is not in accordance with the truth of things. If language be not in accordance with the truth of things, affairs cannot be carried on to success. When affairs cannot be carried on to success, proprieties and music do not flourish. When proprieties and music do not flourish, punishments will not be properly awarded. When punishments are not properly awarded, the people do not know how to move hand or foot. Therefore a superior man considers it necessary that the names he uses may be spoken appropriately, and also that what he speaks may be carried out appropriately. What the superior man requires is just that in his words there may be nothing incorrect.

— Confucius, Analects, Book XIII, Chapter 3, verses 4–7, Analect 13.3, translated by James Legge[18]

The teaching of Confucius consist of five basic relationships in life:

In the above relationships, Confucius teaches that righteous, considerate, kind, benevolent, and gentle treatment should be applied by the former to the latter. And that with the application of such practices in day-to-day life, societal problems would be solved and righteous government would be achieved. The carrying out of these relational duties would equate the proper channeling of li and the correct use of zhèngmíng congruent to Confucius' teachings leading to the envisioned path of his doctrine; a moral and efficient society and individuals who have achieved the ascension to superior human beings through the principles of li and jen. The proper operation of oneself ultimately depends on the role of zhèngmíng; essentially a circle of dependency in terms of the practice and application of principles and ways.[19]

In Confucianism, the Rectification of Names means that "things in actual fact should be made to accord with the implications attached to them by names, the prerequisites for correct living and even efficient government being that all classes of society should accord to what they ought to be".[20] Without the rectification of names, different words would have different actions. This essentially means for every action, there is a word that describes that action. The belief is that by following the Rectification of Names, one would be following the correct/right path. The rectification of names also calls for a standard language in which ancient rulers could impose laws that everyone could understand to avoid confusion.

Each person has a social standing and a social name. With their social names comes responsibilities and duties. Ruler, minister, father and son all have social names therefore need to fulfill their required social duties of respect (The rectification of names). For example, in the study of Chinese culture a child only speaks when a parent permits them to speak.[21]

Following orders from a person of authority means that you are showing respect, therefore that you are following the Rectification of Names without explicitly acknowledging it. Confucius' belief in the Rectification of Names is still practiced in today's society, for example when a teacher asks a student to address a visitor, that student will follow the instructions.

Xunzi

Nets are for catching fish; after one gets the fish, one forgets the net. Traps are for catching rabbits; after one gets the rabbit, one forgets the trap. Words are for getting meaning; after one gets the meaning, one forgets the words. Where can I find people who have forgotten words, and have a word with them?

— Zhuangzi, Ch. 26

Xun Zi wrote a chapter on "The Rectification of Names" developing a theme that had been introduced by Confucius saying: "Let the ruler be ruler, the subject subject; let the father be father, and the son son."[22] Chapter 22, "on the Rectification of Names", claims the ancient sage kings chose names (Chinese: ; pinyin: míng) that directly corresponded with actualities (Chinese: ; pinyin: shí), but later generations confused terminology, coined new nomenclature, and thus could no longer distinguish right from wrong.

Xun Zi not only wrote that chapter on the topic of the rectification of names but went as far as to develop/expand the rectification into a system of logic.[23] Xun Zi, who believed that man's inborn tendencies need to be curbed through education and ritual, countered to Mencius's view that man is innately good. He believed that ethical norms had been invented to rectify mankind. Other philosophers and logicians such as Guanzi, Mozi, and Gongsun Long developed their own theories regarding the rectification. Li in itself can be seen as the root of all this propriety and social etiquette discussed in the rectification of names as the cure to society's problems and the solution to a moral and efficient government and society.

Modern applications

The concept of rectification of names is one of the most basic mottoes of Chinese philosophy. It has been applied to a broad range of issues and mainly resides in the field of politics. This basic yet powerful precept has served as a means for the toppling and reforming of dynasties. In today's society, the rectification of names is being used popularly with government decisions.

Backed by strong public demands, Taiwan during Democratic Progressive Party administrations puts effort into reviewing the names of state-owned enterprises and government entities to preserve their unique identity from Chinese influence.[24] For those who still practice the traditional Confucian approach to ethics and social morality, the rectification of names has an impact in the way society is structured. According to Xuezhi Guo, "Rectification of names also implies the promotion and development of an elaborately differentiated system of status based on social obligations".[25]

Notes

  1. ^ Oldstone-Moore, Jennifer (2002). Confucianism. New York: Oxford University Press, Incorporated. pp. 54–60.
  • ^ Taylor, Rodney L.; Choy, Howard (2003). The Illustrated Encyclopedia of Confucianism. Vol. 1 (1 ed.). New York: The Rosen Group, Incorporated. pp. 48–50.
  • ^ Eno, R. "Legalism and Huang-Lao Thought" (PDF). Indiana University.
  • ^ a b c Chad Hansen. Philosophy of Language in Classical China.
  • ^ a b A.C. Graham 1989. p. 284. Disputers of the Tao.
  • ^ Zhenbin Sun 2015. p. 18. Language, Discourse, and Praxis in Ancient China.
  • ^ a b c Chad Hansen, 1992 pp. 348–349 A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought
  • ^ Chad Hansen. Shen Buhai.
  • ^ Bo Mou 2009 p. 143. Routledge History of Chinese Philosophy Volume 3.
  • ^ Fraser, Chris, "Mohism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
  • ^ Bo Mou 2009 pp. 145,147. Routledge History of Chinese Philosophy Volume 3.
  • ^ Bo Mou 2009 p. 143. Routledge History of Chinese Philosophy Volume 3.
  • ^ Zhongying Cheng 1991 p. 315. New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy.
  • ^ Makeham, J. (1990) pp. 87,89. The Legalistic Concept of Hsing-Ming: An Example of the Contribution of Archaeological Evidence to the Re-Interpretation of Transmitted Texts. Monumenta Serica, 39, 87–114. doi:10.1080/02549948.1990.11731214. JSTOR 40726902.
  • ^ Creel, 1974 pp. 33, 68–69. Shen Pu-hai: A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B.C.
  • ^ Jacques Gernet 1982 p. 91. A History of Chinese Civilization.
  • ^ R. Eno 2010. Indiana University, Early Chinese Thought p. 374. Zhuangzi.
  • ^ Legge, James (1971). Confucian analects: The great learning, and The doctrine of the mean. Dover Publications. pp. 263–264. ISBN 9780486227467.
  • ^ Hopfe, Lewis M. (2006). Religions of the World. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall. pp. 178–85.
  • ^ Steinkraus, Warren (1980). "Socrates, Confucius, and the Rectification of Names". Philosophy East and West. 30 (2): 261–64. doi:10.2307/1398850. JSTOR 1398850.
  • ^ Bailey, Benjamin (1997). "Communication of Respect in Interethnic Service Encounters". Language in Society. 26 (3): 327–356. doi:10.1017/s0047404500019497. JSTOR 4168775. S2CID 145738082.
  • ^ Staal, Frits (1979). "Oriental Ideas on the Origin of Language". Journal of the American Oriental Society. 99 (1): 1–14. doi:10.2307/598944. JSTOR 598944.
  • ^ Goldin, Paul R. (2018). "Xunzi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • ^ Cripps, Karla; Deng, Shawn (2020-04-15). "Taiwan's largest airline considers a name change". CNN. Retrieved 2020-07-05.
  • ^ Guo, Xuezhi (2002). The Ideal Chinese Political Leader. Westport, Connecticut: Praeger Publishers, an imprint of Greenwood Publishing Group. p. 30.
  • Further reading

    External links


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Rectification_of_names&oldid=1133949917"

    Categories: 
    Confucianism
    Names
    Social philosophy
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Articles containing Chinese-language text
     



    This page was last edited on 16 January 2023, at 07:19 (UTC).

    This version of the page has been revised. Besides normal editing, the reason for revision may have been that this version contains factual inaccuracies, vandalism, or material not compatible with the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki