Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Hume, Kant and Bourdieu  





2 Bad taste  





3 See also  





4 Notes  





5 References  














Aesthetic taste






العربية
Беларуская
Български
Català
Чӑвашла
Čeština
Deutsch
Español
Français
Հայերեն
Italiano

Nederlands
Norsk bokmål
Polski
Română
Русский
Slovenčina
Suomi
Svenska
Українська


 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikiquote
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


For Kant, beauty is not a property of any object, but an aesthetic judgement based on a subjective feeling.

Inaesthetics, the concept of taste has been the interest of philosophers such as Plato, Hume, and Kant. It is defined by the ability to make valid judgments about an object's aesthetic value. However, these judgments are deficient in objectivity, creating the 'paradox of taste'. The term 'taste' is used because these judgments are similarly made when one physically tastes food.[1]

Hume, Kant and Bourdieu[edit]

David Hume addressed the subject of aesthetic taste in an essay entitled “Of the Standard of Taste”, one of four essays published in his Four Dissertations in 1757.[2] "Of the Standard of Taste" is highly regarded for its insights into aesthetics. While Hume is generally seen as an empiricist, in matters of taste, he can be classified as an ideal observer theorist, allowing for individual and cultural preferences. Hume distinguishes between sentiments, always correct as they reference only themselves, and determinations, which can be incorrect as they refer to something beyond. Beauty, for Hume, is "no quality in things themselves: It exists merely in the mind which contemplates them; and each mind perceives a different beauty".[3] This, according to Hume, makes judgments of beauty and taste sentiments rather than determinations.

Hume argues that beauty lies in the mind, not the object, and opinions about beauty are influenced by cultural conventions, subject to change. He introduces the concept of a true judge, an individual with "strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by comparison, and cleared of all prejudice."[4] The combined opinions of these rare individuals form the standard of taste, existing within them. This standard is not to be confused with contemporary art critics; the true judge does not apply a standard to objects but possesses ideal perception, enhancing their ability to appreciate beauty.[5] Hume suggests that improving perception leads to better taste.

For Immanuel Kant, as discussed in his Critique of Judgment, beauty is not a property of any object, but an aesthetic judgement based on a subjective feeling. He claims that a genuine good taste does exist, though it could not be empirically identified. The validity of a judgement is not to be ascertained by means of the general view of the majority or some specific social group because taste is both personal and beyond reasoning. Nonetheless, Kant stresses that our preferences, even on generally liked things, do not justify the objectivity of our judgements.[6]

Bourdieu argued against the Kantian view of pure aesthetics, stating that the legitimate taste of the society is the taste of the ruling class.[citation needed] This position also rejects the idea of genuine good taste, as the legitimate taste is merely a class taste. This idea was also proposed by Simmel, who noted that the upper classes abandon fashions as they are adopted by lower ones.[citation needed]

Bad taste[edit]

Bad taste (also poor tasteorvulgarity) is generally used to deride individuals with 'poor' aesthetic judgment.[7] Bad taste can become a respected and cultivated (if perhaps defiant and belligerent) aesthetic, for example in the works of filmmaker John Waters, sculptor Jeff Koons, or the popular McMansion style of architecture.

A contemporary view—a retrospective review of literature—is that "a good deal of dramatic verse written during the Elizabethan and Jacobean periods is in poor taste because it is bombast [high-sounding language with little meaning]".[8]

Grayck argues that individuals can only be judged as having poor taste if their tastes are informed by the aesthetics education they received.[7]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Bonard, Constant; Cova, Florian; Humbert-Droz, Steve (2021). "De gustibus est disputandum: An empirical investigation of the folk concept of aesthetic taste". PsyArVix Preprints – via PsyArVix Preprints.
  • ^ Hume, David (1757). Four Dissertations (1st ed.). London: A. Millar in the Strand.
  • ^ Hume, David (1985). Miller, Eugene F. (ed.). Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary (Revised ed.). Liberty Fund. p. 230.
  • ^ "Internet History Sourcebooks: Modern History". sourcebooks.fordham.edu. Retrieved 30 December 2023.
  • ^ "Aesthetic Taste | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 30 December 2023.
  • ^ Gronow, Jukka (1997). Sociology of Taste. London: Routledge. pp. 11, 87. ISBN 0-415-13294-0.
  • ^ a b Gracyk, Theodore A. (1 April 1990). "Having Bad Taste". The British Journal of Aesthetics. 30 (2): 117–131. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/30.2.117.
  • ^ Abrams, M. H. (1998). "Vulgarity". Dictionary of Literary Terms and Literary Theory. Penguin. p. 976. ISBN 978-0-631-20271-4.
  • References[edit]

    • Arsel, Zeynep; Jonathan Bean (2013). "Taste Regimes and Market-Mediated Practice". Journal of Consumer Research. 39 (5): 899–917. doi:10.1086/666595.
  • Bourdieu, Pierre (1984). Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-04546-0.
  • Bourdieu, Pierre (1986). "The Forms of Capital". In Richardson, John G (ed.). Handbook of Theory and Research for the Sociology of Education. New York: Greenwood Press. ISBN 0-313-23529-5.
  • Bragg, Melvyn (25 October 2007), Taste, In Our Time, BBC Radio 4, retrieved 18 September 2010
  • Ekelund, Robert B. Jr.; Hébert, Robert F. (1990). A History of Economic Theory and Method. 3rd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill Publishing Company. ISBN 0-07-019416-5.
  • Friedman, Sam; Kuipers, Giselinde (2013). "The divisive power of humour: Comedy, taste and symbolic boundaries" (PDF). Cultural Sociology. 7 (2): 179–195. doi:10.1177/1749975513477405. S2CID 53362319.
  • Gronow, Jukka (1997). Sociology of Taste. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-13294-0.
  • Hennion, Antoine (2007). "Those Things That Hold Us Together: Taste and Sociology". Cultural Sociology. 1 (1). London: Sage: 97–114.
  • Holt, Douglas B. (June 1998). "Does Cultural Capital Structure American Consumption?"". The Journal of Consumer Research. 25 (1): 1–25.
  • Horkheimer, Max; Adorno, Theodor W (1982). Dialectic of the Enlightenment. New York: The Continuum publishing Corporation. ISBN 0-8264-0093-0.
  • Koehrsen, Jens (2018). "Religious Tastes and Styles as Markers of Class Belonging" (PDF). Sociology. doi:10.1177/0038038517722288. S2CID 149369482.
  • Outwaite, William; Bottonmore, Tom (1996). The Blackwell Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Social Thought. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
  • Simmel, Georg (May 1957). "Fashion". The American Journal of Sociology. 62 (6): 541–558.
  • Slater, Don (1997). Consumer Culture and Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press. ISBN 978-0-7456-0304-9.
  • Spicher, Michael R. "Aesthetic Taste". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Stern, Jane; Stern, Michael (1990). The Encyclopedia of Bad Taste. New York: Harper Collins. ISBN 0-06-016470-0.
  • Vercelloni, Luca (2016). The Invention of Taste. A Cultural Account of Desire, Delight and Disgust in Fashion, Food and Art. London: Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4742-7360-2.
  • icon Society

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Aesthetic_taste&oldid=1226980022"

    Categories: 
    Sociological terminology
    Concepts in aesthetics
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description matches Wikidata
    Use dmy dates from March 2020
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from August 2023
    Articles containing Latin-language text
    Articles containing Catalan-language text
    Articles containing Italian-language text
     



    This page was last edited on 2 June 2024, at 22:49 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki