Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Principle  





2 Acceptance  





3 History  





4 See also  





5 Notes and references  





6 Sources  





7 External links  














KK thesis







Svenska
 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


The KK thesisorKK principle (also known as epistemic transparencyorpositive introspection[1][2]) is a principleofepistemic logic which states that "If you know that P is the case then you know that you know that P is the case."[3] This means that one cannot know that P is, if one does not know whether one's knowledge of P is correct.[4] Its application in science can be expressed in the way that it must not only justify its knowledge claims but it must also justify its method of justifying.[5] The principle is also described as knowledge-reflexivity contention.[6]

Principle

[edit]

In formal notation, the principle can be stated as:『Kp→KKp』(literally: "Knowing p implies the knowing of knowing p").[7] It is said that the wide acceptance of the thesis steered many philosophers of science towards skepticism since the thesis features infinite regress and that to know is interpreted as "to know with certainty that one knows".[4] The principle also holds that informational independence has epistemological consequences.[8] An application of the principle may involve Hume's skepticism, which holds that it is not possible to know the induction hypothesis needed to determine the derivative knowledge that P from what is already known. This finally leads to the Humean skeptical conclusion if it is attained using KK hypothesis.[4]

An account goes as far as saying that the thesis is false due to these reasons since any argument that depends upon it is unsatisfactory.[9] It is also said that the thesis had been disputed since the introduction of the epistemic logic by Jaakko Hintikka in 1962.[8] There are contemporary epistemologists who pointed out that skepticism can be rejected by rejecting the KK principle but to do so means one is also rejecting the idea of knowledge.[10]

Acceptance

[edit]

While major philosophers of the past (Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, Shopenhauer) endorsed the principle, in the beginning of the 21st century the acceptance of the KK thesis widely varies between the epistemologists. Some reject it outright: Daniel Greco (who might be supporting the thesis) says that principle had "seen better days", Louise Antony speaks of it as "roundly rejected". Most externalists also reject the thesis, but statements by internalists, while not explicitly declaring acceptance, contain supportive language.[2]

Timothy Williamson presented a "very influential" attack on the KK principle in 2000 in his book "Knowledge and its Limits".[2]

History

[edit]

The KK thesis has been associated with the notion of the infallibility of knowledge since ancient philosophers sometimes characterized the latter according to the former's terms.[11] Plato's view on infallibility, for example, can be approached according to its framework, particularly concerning his position stated in Theatetus that truth can only be attained by infallibly knowing it.[11]

Jaakko Hintikka, argued that the plausibility of the KK thesis turns upon the acceptance of a strong notion of knowledge and that it is also in part constitutive of that notion.[12] He traced the thesis' earliest iteration in Plato's Charmides and the Book of LambdaofAristotle's Metaphysics.[12] He also cited examples drawn from other points of philosophical history, citing the works of Augustine, Averoes, Thomas Aquinas, and Baruch Spinoza, among others.[13] In response to the critique about the implausibility of the KK thesis, Hintikka stated that it is not an important point because what matters is that the principle is able "to capture a strong sense of knowledge".[14]

Modern formulations of the thesis sometimes include qualifications requiring, for example, "normal conditions for psychological self-knowledge".[2]

See also

[edit]

Notes and references

[edit]
  1. ^ Cresto 2012, p. 923.
  • ^ a b c d Azzouni 2020, p. 171.
  • ^ Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2004). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. Blackwell Publishing Limited. p. 776. ISBN 978-1-4051-0679-5.
  • ^ a b c Hunt, Shelby (2003). Controversy in Marketing Theory: For Reason, Realism, Truth, and Objectivity. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe. p. 94. ISBN 0765609312.
  • ^ Hunt, Shelby (2003). Controversy in Marketing Theory: For Reason, Realism, Truth, and Objectivity. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe. p. 94. ISBN 0765609312.
  • ^ Rescher, Nicholas (2005). Epistemic Logic: A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. p. 22. ISBN 0-8229-4246-1.
  • ^ Carruthers, Peter (1992). Human Knowledge and Human Nature: A New Introduction to an Ancient Debate. Oxford University Press, USA. p. 208. ISBN 978-0-19-875102-1.
  • ^ a b Rahman, Shahid; Symons, John; Gabbay, Dov M.; bendegem, jean paul van (2009). Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. p. 92. ISBN 978-1-4020-2807-6.
  • ^ Barnes, Jonathan (2007). The Toils of Scepticism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 142. ISBN 9780521043878.
  • ^ Doyle, Casey; Milburn, Joseph; Pritchard, Duncan (2019). New Issues in Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxon: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-60355-3.
  • ^ a b Gerson, Lloyd P. (2009). Ancient Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 56. ISBN 9780521871396.
  • ^ a b Lagerlund, Henrik (2007). Forming the Mind: Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 94–95. ISBN 9781402060830.
  • ^ Ditmarsch, Hans van; Sandu, Gabriel (2018-01-31). Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. p. 418. ISBN 9783319628646.
  • ^ Bogdan, R. (1987). Jaakko Hintikka. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. p. 310. ISBN 9789027724021.
  • Sources

    [edit]
    [edit]
    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=KK_thesis&oldid=1213271161"

    Categories: 
    Epistemic logic
    Principles
    Concepts in epistemology
    Hidden category: 
    Articles with Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy links
     



    This page was last edited on 12 March 2024, at 01:09 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki