Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Description  



1.1  Calculating the overall ranking  





1.2  Summary matrix  







2 Example  





3 Characteristics  



3.1  Satisfied criteria for all Condorcet methods  





3.2  Additional satisfied criteria  





3.3  Failed criteria for all Condorcet methods  





3.4  Additional failed criteria  







4 Calculation methods and computational complexity  





5 History  





6 Comparison table  





7 Notes  





8 External links  














KemenyYoung method







Add links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


The Kemeny–Young method is an electoral system that uses ranked ballots and pairwise comparison counts to identify the most popular choices in an election. It is a Condorcet method because if there is a Condorcet winner, it will always be ranked as the most popular choice.

This method assigns a score for each possible sequence, where each sequence considers which choice might be most popular, which choice might be second-most popular, which choice might be third-most popular, and so on down to which choice might be least-popular. The sequence that has the highest score is the winning sequence, and the first choice in the winning sequence is the most popular choice. (As explained below, ties can occur at any ranking level.)

The Kemeny–Young method is also known as the Kemeny rule, VoteFair popularity ranking, the maximum likelihood method, and the median relation.

Description[edit]

The Kemeny–Young method uses preferential ballots on which voters rank choices according to their order of preference. A voter is allowed to rank more than one choice at the same preference level.[citation needed] Unranked choices are usually interpreted as least-preferred.

Kemeny–Young calculations are usually done in two steps. The first step is to create a matrix or table that counts pairwise voter preferences. The second step is to test all possible rankings, calculate a score for each such ranking, and compare the scores. Each ranking score equals the sum of the pairwise counts that apply to that ranking.

The ranking that has the largest score is identified as the overall ranking. (If more than one ranking has the same largest score, all these possible rankings are tied, and typically the overall ranking involves one or more ties.)

Another way to view the ordering is that it is the one which minimizes the sum of the Kendall tau distances (bubble sort distance) to the voters' lists.

In order to demonstrate how an individual preference order is converted into a tally table, it is worth considering the following example. Suppose that a single voter has a choice among four candidates (i.e. Elliot, Meredith, Roland, and Selden) and has the following preference order:

Preference
order
Choice
First Elliot
Second Roland
Third Meredith or Selden
(equal preference)

These preferences can be expressed in a tally table. A tally table, which arranges all the pairwise counts in three columns, is useful for counting (tallying) ballot preferences and calculating ranking scores. The center column tracks when a voter indicates more than one choice at the same preference level. The above preference order can be expressed as the following tally table:[citation needed]

All possible pairs
of choice names
Number of votes with indicated preference
Prefer X over Y Equal preference Prefer Y over X
X = Selden
Y = Meredith
0 +1 vote 0
X = Selden
Y = Elliot
0 0 +1 vote
X = Selden
Y = Roland
0 0 +1 vote
X = Meredith
Y = Elliot
0 0 +1 vote
X = Meredith
Y = Roland
0 0 +1 vote
X = Elliot
Y = Roland
+1 vote 0 0

Now suppose that multiple voters had voted on those four candidates. After all ballots have been counted, the same type of tally table can be used to summarize all the preferences of all the voters. Here is an example for a case that has 100 voters:

All possible pairs
of choice names
Number of votes with indicated preference
Prefer X over Y Equal preference Prefer Y over X
X = Selden
Y = Meredith
50 10 40
X = Selden
Y = Elliot
40 0 60
X = Selden
Y = Roland
40 0 60
X = Meredith
Y = Elliot
40 0 60
X = Meredith
Y = Roland
30 0 70
X = Elliot
Y = Roland
30 0 70


The sum of the counts in each row must equal the total number of votes.

After the tally table has been completed, each possible ranking of choices is examined in turn, and its ranking score is calculated by adding the appropriate number from each row of the tally table. For example, the possible ranking:

  1. Elliot
  2. Roland
  3. Meredith
  4. Selden

satisfies the preferences Elliot > Roland, Elliot > Meredith, Elliot > Selden, Roland > Meredith, Roland > Selden, and Meredith > Selden. The respective scores, taken from the table, are

giving a total ranking score of 30 + 60 + 60 + 70 + 60 + 40 = 320.

Calculating the overall ranking[edit]

After the scores for every possible ranking have been calculated, the ranking that has the largest score can be identified, and becomes the overall ranking. In this case, the overall ranking is:

  1. Roland
  2. Elliot
  3. Selden
  4. Meredith

with a ranking score of 370.

If there are cycles or ties, more than one possible ranking can have the same largest score. Cycles are resolved by producing a single overall ranking where some of the choices are tied.[clarification needed]

Summary matrix[edit]

After the overall ranking has been calculated, the pairwise comparison counts can be arranged in a summary matrix, as shown below, in which the choices appear in the winning order from most popular (top and left) to least popular (bottom and right). This matrix layout does not include the equal-preference pairwise counts that appear in the tally table:[1]

... over Roland ... over Elliot ... over Selden ... over Meredith
Prefer Roland ... - 70 60 70
Prefer Elliot ... 30 - 60 60
Prefer Selden ... 40 40 - 50
Prefer Meredith ... 30 40 40 -

In this summary matrix, the largest ranking score equals the sum of the counts in the upper-right, triangular half of the matrix (shown here in bold, with a green background). No other possible ranking can have a summary matrix that yields a higher sum of numbers in the upper-right, triangular half. (If it did, that would be the overall ranking.)

In this summary matrix, the sum of the numbers in the lower-left, triangular half of the matrix (shown here with a red background) are a minimum. The academic papers by John Kemeny and Peyton Young[2][3] refer to finding this minimum sum, which is called the Kemeny score, and which is based on how many voters oppose (rather than support) each pairwise order:

Method First-place winner
Kemeny–Young Roland
Condorcet Roland
Instant runoff voting Elliot or Selden
(depending on how the second-round tie is handled)
Plurality Selden

Example[edit]

  • t
  • e
  • Tennessee and its four major cities: Memphis in the far west; Nashville in the center; Chattanooga in the east; and Knoxville in the far northeast

    Suppose that Tennessee is holding an election on the location of its capital. The population is concentrated around four major cities. All voters want the capital to be as close to them as possible. The options are:

    The preferences of each region's voters are:

    42% of voters
    Far-West
    26% of voters
    Center
    15% of voters
    Center-East
    17% of voters
    Far-East
    1. Memphis
    2. Nashville
    3. Chattanooga
    4. Knoxville
    1. Nashville
    2. Chattanooga
    3. Knoxville
    4. Memphis
    1. Chattanooga
    2. Knoxville
    3. Nashville
    4. Memphis
    1. Knoxville
    2. Chattanooga
    3. Nashville
    4. Memphis


    This matrix summarizes the corresponding pairwise comparison counts:

    ... over
    Memphis
    ... over
    Nashville
    ... over
    Chattanooga
    ... over
    Knoxville
    Prefer
    Memphis ...
    - 42% 42% 42%
    Prefer
    Nashville ...
    58% - 68% 68%
    Prefer
    Chattanooga ...
    58% 32% - 83%
    Prefer
    Knoxville ...
    58% 32% 17% -


    The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table:

    All possible pairs
    of choice names
    Number of votes with indicated preference
    Prefer X over Y Equal preference Prefer Y over X
    X = Memphis
    Y = Nashville
    42% 0 58%
    X = Memphis
    Y = Chattanooga
    42% 0 58%
    X = Memphis
    Y = Knoxville
    42% 0 58%
    X = Nashville
    Y = Chattanooga
    68% 0 32%
    X = Nashville
    Y = Knoxville
    68% 0 32%
    X = Chattanooga
    Y = Knoxville
    83% 0 17%


    The ranking score for the possible ranking of Memphis first, Nashville second, Chattanooga third, and Knoxville fourth equals (the unit-less number) 345, which is the sum of the following annotated numbers.

    42% (of the voters) prefer Memphis over Nashville
    42% prefer Memphis over Chattanooga
    42% prefer Memphis over Knoxville
    68% prefer Nashville over Chattanooga
    68% prefer Nashville over Knoxville
    83% prefer Chattanooga over Knoxville


    This table lists all the ranking scores:

    First
    choice
    Second
    choice
    Third
    choice
    Fourth
    choice
    Ranking
    score
    Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville 345
    Memphis Nashville Knoxville Chattanooga 279
    Memphis Chattanooga Nashville Knoxville 309
    Memphis Chattanooga Knoxville Nashville 273
    Memphis Knoxville Nashville Chattanooga 243
    Memphis Knoxville Chattanooga Nashville 207
    Nashville Memphis Chattanooga Knoxville 361
    Nashville Memphis Knoxville Chattanooga 295
    Nashville Chattanooga Memphis Knoxville 377
    Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville Memphis 393
    Nashville Knoxville Memphis Chattanooga 311
    Nashville Knoxville Chattanooga Memphis 327
    Chattanooga Memphis Nashville Knoxville 325
    Chattanooga Memphis Knoxville Nashville 289
    Chattanooga Nashville Memphis Knoxville 341
    Chattanooga Nashville Knoxville Memphis 357
    Chattanooga Knoxville Memphis Nashville 305
    Chattanooga Knoxville Nashville Memphis 321
    Knoxville Memphis Nashville Chattanooga 259
    Knoxville Memphis Chattanooga Nashville 223
    Knoxville Nashville Memphis Chattanooga 275
    Knoxville Nashville Chattanooga Memphis 291
    Knoxville Chattanooga Memphis Nashville 239
    Knoxville Chattanooga Nashville Memphis 255


    The largest ranking score is 393, and this score is associated with the following possible ranking, so this ranking is also the overall ranking:

    Preference
    order
    Choice
    First Nashville
    Second Chattanooga
    Third Knoxville
    Fourth Memphis


    If a single winner is needed, the first choice, Nashville, is chosen. (In this example Nashville is the Condorcet winner.)

    The summary matrix below arranges the pairwise counts in order from most popular (top and left) to least popular (bottom and right):

    ... over Nashville ... ... over Chattanooga ... ... over Knoxville ... ... over Memphis ...
    Prefer Nashville ... - 68% 68% 58%
    Prefer Chattanooga ... 32% - 83% 58%
    Prefer Knoxville ... 32% 17% - 58%
    Prefer Memphis ... 42% 42% 42% -


    In this arrangement the largest ranking score (393) equals the sum of the counts in bold, which are in the upper-right, triangular half of the matrix (with a green background).

    Characteristics[edit]

    In all cases that do not result in an exact tie, the Kemeny–Young method identifies a most-popular choice, second-most popular choice, and so on.

    A tie can occur at any preference level. Except in some cases where circular ambiguities are involved, the Kemeny–Young method only produces a tie at a preference level when the number of voters with one preference exactly matches the number of voters with the opposite preference.

    Satisfied criteria for all Condorcet methods[edit]

    All Condorcet methods, including the Kemeny–Young method, satisfy these criteria:

    Non-imposition
    There are voter preferences that can yield every possible overall order-of-preference result, including ties at any combination of preference levels.
    Condorcet criterion
    If there is a choice that wins all pairwise contests, then this choice wins.
    Majority criterion
    If a majority of voters strictly prefer choice X to every other choice, then choice X is identified as the most popular.
    Non-dictatorship
    A single voter cannot control the outcome in all cases.

    Additional satisfied criteria[edit]

    The Kemeny–Young method also satisfies these criteria:

    Unrestricted domain
    Identifies the overall order of preference for all the choices. The method does this for all possible sets of voter preferences and always produces the same result for the same set of voter preferences.
    Pareto efficiency
    Any pairwise preference expressed by every voter results in the preferred choice being ranked higher than the less-preferred choice.
    Monotonicity
    If voters increase a choice's preference level, the ranking result either does not change or the promoted choice increases in overall popularity.
    Smith criterion
    The most popular choice is a member of the Smith set, which is the smallest nonempty set of choices such that every member of the set is pairwise preferred to every choice not in the Smith set.
    Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives
    If choice X is not in the Smith set, adding or withdrawing choice X does not change a result in which choice Y is identified as most popular.
    Reinforcement
    If all the ballots are divided into separate races and the overall ranking for the separate races are the same, then the same ranking occurs when all the ballots are combined.[4]
    Reversal symmetry
    If the preferences on every ballot are inverted, then the previously most popular choice must not remain the most popular choice.

    Failed criteria for all Condorcet methods[edit]

    In common with all Condorcet methods, the Kemeny–Young method fails these criteria (which means the described criteria do not apply to the Kemeny–Young method):

    Independence of irrelevant alternatives
    Adding or withdrawing choice X does not change a result in which choice Y is identified as most popular.
    Invulnerability to burying
    A voter cannot displace a choice from most popular by giving the choice an insincerely low ranking.
    Invulnerability to compromising
    A voter cannot cause a choice to become the most popular by giving the choice an insincerely high ranking.
    Participation
    Adding ballots that rank choice X over choice Y never cause choice Y, instead of choice X, to become most popular.
    Later-no-harm
    Ranking an additional choice (that was otherwise unranked) cannot displace a choice from being identified as the most popular.
    Consistency
    If all the ballots are divided into separate races and choice X is identified as the most popular in every such race, then choice X is the most popular when all the ballots are combined.
    Sincere favorite criterion
    The optimal voting strategy for an individual should always include giving their favorite candidate maximum support.

    Additional failed criteria[edit]

    The Kemeny–Young method also fails these criteria (which means the described criteria do not apply to the Kemeny–Young method):

    Independence of clones
    Offering a larger number of similar choices, instead of offering only a single such choice, does not change the probability that one of these choices is identified as most popular.
    Invulnerability to push-over
    A voter cannot cause choice X to become the most popular by giving choice Y an insincerely high ranking.
    Schwartz
    The choice identified as most popular is a member of the Schwartz set.
    Polynomial runtime[5]
    An algorithm is known to determine the winner using this method in a runtime that is polynomial in the number of choices.

    Calculation methods and computational complexity[edit]

    An algorithm for computing a Kemeny-Young ranking in time polynomial in the number of candidates is not known, and unlikely to exist since the problem is NP-hard[5] even if there are just 4 voters (even)[6][7] or 7 voters (odd).[8]

    It has been reported[9] that calculation methods based on integer programming sometimes allowed the computation of full rankings for votes on as many as 40 candidates in seconds. However, certain 40-candidate 5-voter Kemeny elections generated at random were not solvable on a 3 GHz Pentium computer in a useful time bound in 2006.[9]

    The Kemeny–Young method can be formulated as an instance of a more abstract problem, of finding weighted feedback arc setsintournament graphs.[10] As such, many methods for the computation of feedback arc sets can be applied to this problem, including a variant of the Held–Karp algorithm that can compute the Kemeny–Young ranking of candidates in time , significantly faster for many candidates than the factorial time of testing all rankings.[11][12] There exists a polynomial-time approximation scheme for computing a Kemeny-Young ranking,[13] and there also exists a parameterized subexponential-time algorithm with running time O*(2O(OPT)) for computing such a ranking.[10]

    History[edit]

    The Kemeny–Young method was developed by John Kemeny in 1959.[2]

    In 1978, Peyton Young and Arthur Levenglick axiomatically characterized the method, showing that it is the unique neutral method satisfying consistency and the so-called quasi-Condorcet criterion.[3] It can also be characterized using consistency and a monotonicity property.[14] In other papers,[15] [16] [17] [18] Young adopted an epistemic approach to preference aggregation: he supposed that there was an objectively 'correct', but unknown preference order over the alternatives, and voters receive noisy signals of this true preference order (cf. Condorcet's jury theorem.) Using a simple probabilistic model for these noisy signals, Young showed that the Kemeny–Young method was the maximum likelihood estimator of the true preference order. Young further argues that Condorcet himself was aware of the Kemeny-Young rule and its maximum-likelihood interpretation, but was unable to clearly express his ideas.

    In the papers by John Kemeny and Peyton Young, the Kemeny scores use counts of how many voters oppose, rather than support, each pairwise preference,[2][3] but the smallest such score identifies the same overall ranking.

    Since 1991 the method has been promoted under the name "VoteFair popularity ranking" by Richard Fobes.[19]

    Comparison table[edit]

    The following table compares the Kemeny-Young method with other single-winner election methods:


    Notes[edit]

    1. ^ The numbers in this example are adapted from Sample election used in Wikipedia Archived 2017-03-30 at the Wayback Machine.
  • ^ a b c John Kemeny, "Mathematics without numbers", Daedalus 88 (1959), pp. 577–591.
  • ^ a b c H. P. Young and A. Levenglick, "A Consistent Extension of Condorcet's Election Principle", SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics 35, no. 2 (1978), pp. 285–300.
  • ^ Giuseppe Munda, "Social multi-criteria evaluation for a sustainable economy", p. 124.
  • ^ a b J. Bartholdi III, C. A. Tovey, and M. A. Trick, "Voting schemes for which it can be difficult to tell who won the election", Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 6, No. 2 (1989), pp. 157–165.
  • ^ C. Dwork, R. Kumar, M. Naor, D. Sivakumar. Rank Aggregation Methods for the Web, WWW10, 2001
  • ^ Biedl, Therese; Brandenburg, Franz J.; Deng, Xiaotie (2005-09-12). Healy, Patrick; Nikolov, Nikola S. (eds.). Crossings and Permutations. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 1–12. doi:10.1007/11618058_1. ISBN 9783540314257. S2CID 11189107.
  • ^ Bachmeier, Georg; Brandt, Felix; Geist, Christian; Harrenstein, Paul; Kardel, Keyvan; Peters, Dominik; Seedig, Hans Georg (2019-11-01). "k-Majority digraphs and the hardness of voting with a constant number of voters". Journal of Computer and System Sciences. 105: 130–157. arXiv:1704.06304. doi:10.1016/j.jcss.2019.04.005. ISSN 0022-0000. S2CID 2357131.
  • ^ a b Vincent Conitzer, Andrew Davenport, and Jayant Kalagnanam, "Improved bounds for computing Kemeny rankings" (2006).
  • ^ a b Karpinski, M. and Schudy, W., "Faster Algorithms for Feedback Arc Set Tournament, Kemeny Rank Aggregation and Betweenness Tournament", in: Cheong, O., Chwa, K.-Y., and Park, K. (Eds.): ISAAC 2010, Part I, LNCS 6506, pp. 3-14.
  • ^ Lawler, E. (1964), "A comment on minimum feedback arc sets", IEEE Transactions on Circuit Theory, 11 (2): 296–297, doi:10.1109/tct.1964.1082291
  • ^ Bodlaender, Hans L.; Fomin, Fedor V.; Koster, Arie M. C. A.; Kratsch, Dieter; Thilikos, Dimitrios M. (2012), "A note on exact algorithms for vertex ordering problems on graphs", Theory of Computing Systems, 50 (3): 420–432, doi:10.1007/s00224-011-9312-0, hdl:1956/4556, MR 2885638, S2CID 253742611
  • ^ "How to Rank with Few Errors". http://cs.brown.edu/~claire/stoc07.pdf
  • ^ Can, Burak; Storcken, Ton (2013-03-01). "Update monotone preference rules" (PDF). Mathematical Social Sciences. 65 (2): 136–149. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2012.10.004. ISSN 0165-4896.
  • ^ H. P. Young, "Condorcet's Theory of Voting", American Political Science Review 82, no. 2 (1988), pp. 1231–1244.
  • ^ H. P. Young, "Optimal ranking and choice from pairwise comparisons", in Information pooling and group decision making edited by B. Grofman and G. Owen (1986), JAI Press, pp. 113–122.
  • ^ H. P. Young, "Optimal Voting Rules", Journal of Economic Perspectives 9, no.1 (1995), pp. 51–64.
  • ^ H. P. Young, "Group choice and individual judgements", Chapter 9 of Perspectives on public choice: a handbook, edited by Dennis Mueller (1997) Cambridge UP., pp.181 –200.
  • ^ Richard Fobes, "The Creative Problem Solver's Toolbox", (ISBN 0-9632-2210-4), 1993, pp. 223–225.
  • External links[edit]


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Kemeny–Young_method&oldid=1225085642"

    Categories: 
    Electoral systems
    Monotonic Condorcet methods
    Hidden categories: 
    Webarchive template wayback links
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from January 2015
    Wikipedia articles needing clarification from October 2010
     



    This page was last edited on 22 May 2024, at 08:26 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki