Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Definition  





2 Notation  



2.1  Precedence  







3 Properties  



3.1  Double negation  





3.2  Distributivity  





3.3  Linearity  





3.4  Self dual  





3.5  Negations of quantifiers  







4 Rules of inference  





5 Programming language and ordinary language  





6 Kripke semantics  





7 See also  





8 References  





9 Further reading  





10 External links  














Negation






العربية
Azərbaycanca
Български
Català
Čeština
Dansk
Deutsch
Eesti
Emiliàn e rumagnòl
Español
Esperanto
Euskara
فارسی
Français
Galego

Հայերեն
ि
Hrvatski
Bahasa Indonesia
Italiano
עברית
Қазақша
Latina
Magyar
Македонски
Bahasa Melayu
Nederlands

Norsk bokmål
Piemontèis
Polski
Português
Русский
Shqip
Simple English
Slovenčina
Slovenščina
کوردی
Српски / srpski
Srpskohrvatski / српскохрватски
Svenska
Tagalog

Тоҷикӣ
Türkçe
Українська


 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 

(Redirected from Not sign)

Negation
NOT
Venn diagram of Negation
Definition
Truth table
Logic gate
Normal forms
Disjunctive
Conjunctive
Zhegalkin polynomial
Post's lattices
0-preservingno
1-preservingno
Monotoneno
Affineyes
Self-dualyes
  • t
  • e
  • Inlogic, negation, also called the logical notorlogical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition to another proposition "not ", standing for " is not true", written , or. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when is false, and false when is true.[1][2] Negation is thus a unary logical connective. It may be applied as an operation on notions, propositions, truth values, or semantic values more generally. In classical logic, negation is normally identified with the truth function that takes truthtofalsity (and vice versa). In intuitionistic logic, according to the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, the negation of a proposition is the proposition whose proofs are the refutations of .

    An operand of a negation is a negand,[3]ornegatum.[3]

    Definition

    [edit]

    Classical negation is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition, that produces a value of true when its operand is false, and a value of false when its operand is true. Thus if statement is true, then (pronounced "not P") would then be false; and conversely, if is true, then would be false.

    The truth tableof is as follows:

    True False
    False True

    Negation can be defined in terms of other logical operations. For example, can be defined as (where islogical consequence and isabsolute falsehood). Conversely, one can define as for any proposition Q (where islogical conjunction). The idea here is that any contradiction is false, and while these ideas work in both classical and intuitionistic logic, they do not work in paraconsistent logic, where contradictions are not necessarily false. In classical logic, we also get a further identity, can be defined as , where islogical disjunction.

    Algebraically, classical negation corresponds to complementation in a Boolean algebra, and intuitionistic negation to pseudocomplementation in a Heyting algebra. These algebras provide a semantics for classical and intuitionistic logic.

    Notation

    [edit]

    The negation of a proposition p is notated in different ways, in various contexts of discussion and fields of application. The following table documents some of these variants:

    Notation Plain text Vocalization
    ¬p , 7p[4] Not p
    ~p Not p
    -p Not p
    Enp
    p'
    • p prime,
  • p complement
  • ̅p
    • p bar,
  • Bar p
  • !p
    • Bang p
  • Not p
  • The notation isPolish notation.

    Inset theory, is also used to indicate 'not in the set of': is the set of all members of U that are not members of A.

    Regardless how it is notated or symbolized, the negation can be read as "it is not the case that P", "not that P", or usually more simply as "not P".

    Precedence

    [edit]

    As a way of reducing the number of necessary parentheses, one may introduce precedence rules: ¬ has higher precedence than ∧, ∧ higher than ∨, and ∨ higher than →. So for example, is short for

    Here is a table that shows a commonly used precedence of logical operators.[5]

    Operator Precedence
    1
    2
    3
    4
    5

    Properties

    [edit]

    Double negation

    [edit]

    Within a system of classical logic, double negation, that is, the negation of the negation of a proposition , is logically equivalentto. Expressed in symbolic terms, . In intuitionistic logic, a proposition implies its double negation, but not conversely. This marks one important difference between classical and intuitionistic negation. Algebraically, classical negation is called an involution of period two.

    However, in intuitionistic logic, the weaker equivalence does hold. This is because in intuitionistic logic, is just a shorthand for , and we also have . Composing that last implication with triple negation implies that .

    As a result, in the propositional case, a sentence is classically provable if its double negation is intuitionistically provable. This result is known as Glivenko's theorem.

    Distributivity

    [edit]

    De Morgan's laws provide a way of distributing negation over disjunction and conjunction:

    ,  and
    .

    Linearity

    [edit]

    Let denote the logical xor operation. In Boolean algebra, a linear function is one such that:

    If there exists , , for all .

    Another way to express this is that each variable always makes a difference in the truth-value of the operation, or it never makes a difference. Negation is a linear logical operator.

    Self dual

    [edit]

    InBoolean algebra, a self dual function is a function such that:

    for all . Negation is a self dual logical operator.

    Negations of quantifiers

    [edit]

    Infirst-order logic, there are two quantifiers, one is the universal quantifier (means "for all") and the other is the existential quantifier (means "there exists"). The negation of one quantifier is the other quantifier ( and ). For example, with the predicate P as "x is mortal" and the domain of x as the collection of all humans, means "a person x in all humans is mortal" or "all humans are mortal". The negation of it is , meaning "there exists a person x in all humans who is not mortal", or "there exists someone who lives forever".

    Rules of inference

    [edit]

    There are a number of equivalent ways to formulate rules for negation. One usual way to formulate classical negation in a natural deduction setting is to take as primitive rules of inference negation introduction (from a derivation of to both and , infer ; this rule also being called reductio ad absurdum), negation elimination (from and infer ; this rule also being called ex falso quodlibet), and double negation elimination (from infer ). One obtains the rules for intuitionistic negation the same way but by excluding double negation elimination.

    Negation introduction states that if an absurdity can be drawn as conclusion from then must not be the case (i.e. is false (classically) or refutable (intuitionistically) or etc.). Negation elimination states that anything follows from an absurdity. Sometimes negation elimination is formulated using a primitive absurdity sign . In this case the rule says that from and follows an absurdity. Together with double negation elimination one may infer our originally formulated rule, namely that anything follows from an absurdity.

    Typically the intuitionistic negation of is defined as . Then negation introduction and elimination are just special cases of implication introduction (conditional proof) and elimination (modus ponens). In this case one must also add as a primitive rule ex falso quodlibet.

    Programming language and ordinary language

    [edit]

    As in mathematics, negation is used in computer science to construct logical statements.

    if (!(r == t))
    {
        /*...statements executed when r does NOT equal t...*/
    }
    

    The exclamation mark "!" signifies logical NOT in B, C, and languages with a C-inspired syntax such as C++, Java, JavaScript, Perl, and PHP. "NOT" is the operator used in ALGOL 60, BASIC, and languages with an ALGOL- or BASIC-inspired syntax such as Pascal, Ada, Eiffel and Seed7. Some languages (C++, Perl, etc.) provide more than one operator for negation. A few languages like PL/I and Ratfor use ¬ for negation. Most modern languages allow the above statement to be shortened from if (!(r == t))toif (r != t), which allows sometimes, when the compiler/interpreter is not able to optimize it, faster programs.

    In computer science there is also bitwise negation. This takes the value given and switches all the binary 1s to 0s and 0s to 1s. See bitwise operation. This is often used to create ones' complement or "~" in C or C++ and two's complement (just simplified to "-" or the negative sign since this is equivalent to taking the arithmetic negative value of the number) as it basically creates the opposite (negative value equivalent) or mathematical complement of the value (where both values are added together they create a whole).

    To get the absolute (positive equivalent) value of a given integer the following would work as the "-" changes it from negative to positive (it is negative because "x < 0" yields true)

    unsigned int abs(int x)
    {
        if (x < 0)
            return -x;
        else
            return x;
    }
    

    To demonstrate logical negation:

    unsigned int abs(int x)
    {
        if (!(x < 0))
            return x;
        else
            return -x;
    }
    

    Inverting the condition and reversing the outcomes produces code that is logically equivalent to the original code, i.e. will have identical results for any input (depending on the compiler used, the actual instructions performed by the computer may differ).

    In C (and some other languages descended from C), double negation (!!x) is used as an idiom to convert x to a canonical boolean, ie. an integer with a value of either 0 or 1 and no other. Although any integer other than 0 is logically true in C and 1 is not special in this regard, it is sometimes important to ensure that a canonical value is used, for example for printing or if the number is subsequently used for arithmetic operations.[6]

    The convention of using ! to signify negation occasionally surfaces in ordinary written speech, as computer-related slang for not. For example, the phrase !voting means "not voting". Another example is the phrase !clue which is used as a synonym for "no-clue" or "clueless".[7][8]

    Kripke semantics

    [edit]

    InKripke semantics where the semantic values of formulae are sets of possible worlds, negation can be taken to mean set-theoretic complementation[citation needed] (see also possible world semantics for more).

    See also

    [edit]
  • Ampheck
  • Apophasis
  • Binary opposition
  • Bitwise NOT
  • Contraposition
  • Cyclic negation
  • Negation as failure
  • NOT gate
  • Plato's beard
  • Square of opposition
  • References

    [edit]
    1. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Negation". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2 September 2020.
  • ^ "Logic and Mathematical Statements - Worked Examples". www.math.toronto.edu. Retrieved 2 September 2020.
  • ^ a b Beall, Jeffrey C. (2010). Logic: the basics. The basics (1. publ ed.). London: Routledge. p. 57. ISBN 978-0-203-85155-5.
  • ^ Used as makeshift in early typewriter publications, e.g. Richard E. Ladner (January 1975). "The circuit value problem is log space complete for P". ACM SIGACT News. 7 (101): 18–20. doi:10.1145/990518.990519.
  • ^ O'Donnell, John; Hall, Cordelia; Page, Rex (2007), Discrete Mathematics Using a Computer, Springer, p. 120, ISBN 9781846285981.
  • ^ Egan, David. "Double Negation Operator Convert to Boolean in C". Dev Notes.
  • ^ Raymond, Eric and Steele, Guy. The New Hacker's Dictionary, p. 18 (MIT Press 1996).
  • ^ Munat, Judith. Lexical Creativity, Texts and Context, p. 148 (John Benjamins Publishing, 2007).
  • Further reading

    [edit]
    [edit]
    Tables of Truth of composite clauses

    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Negation&oldid=1232398428"

    Categories: 
    Semantics
    Logical connectives
    Unary operations
    Formal semantics (natural language)
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Use dmy dates from March 2020
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from August 2012
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with example C++ code
     



    This page was last edited on 3 July 2024, at 14:52 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki