Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Biography  





2 Nominalism  





3 Tritheism of Roscelin  





4 Notes  





5 References  



5.1  Citations  





5.2  Bibliography  
















Roscellinus






العربية
Català
Čeština
Dansk
Deutsch
Español
Euskara
فارسی
Français
Gaeilge

Hrvatski
Italiano
עברית
Қазақша
Кыргызча
Latina
Magyar
مصرى
Nederlands

Norsk bokmål
Polski
Português
Русский
Slovenčina
Slovenščina
Srpskohrvatski / српскохрватски
Suomi
Svenska
Türkçe
Українська

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Roscelin of Compiègne (c. 1050 – c. 1121), better known by his Latinized name Roscellinus CompendiensisorRucelinus, was a French philosopher and theologian, often regarded as the founder of nominalism.

Biography[edit]

Roscellinus was born in Compiègne, France. Little is known of his life, and knowledge of his doctrines is mainly derived from Anselm and Abelard. He studied at Soissons and Reims, was afterwards attached to the cathedral of Chartres and became canon of Compiègne. As a monk of Compiègne, he was teaching as early as 1087. He had contact with Lanfranc, Anselm, and St. Ivo of Chartres.

Roscellinus's exposition of Nominalist doctrines, and especially his application to the dogma of the Trinity, attracted broad attention. He maintained that the three persons of the Trinity were not referred to as three substances or Gods only by convention, arguing that if they were really one substance then God the Father and the Holy Spirit would have become incarnate along with God the Son. Roscellinus cited Lanfranc and Anselm in support of this doctrine.

In 1092/1093, however, a council convoked at Soissons by the archbishop of Reims condemned his interpretation and accused Roscellinus of tritheism.[n 1] Roscellinus, out of fear of excommunication and even stoning to death by the orthodox populace, recanted his beliefs, but later returned to professing them.

Roscellinus left for England, but having made himself unpopular by an attack on the doctrines of Anselm, he left the country and repaired to Rome, where he was well received and became reconciled to the Catholic Church. He then returned to France, taught at Tours and Loc-menach (where he had Abelard as a pupil), and finally became canon of Besançon. He is heard of as late as 1121, when he came forward to oppose Abelard's views on the Trinity. He was also sent a letter by Theobald of Étampes in response to his criticisms of the sons of priests.

Of his writings there exists only a letter addressed to Abelard on the Trinity, in which Roscellinus "belittles Abélard and makes merry over his castration."[2] Hauréau brings forward his name in connection with a text, "Sententia de universalibus secundum magistrum R.",[3] but this is a conjecture. His doctrines are attested by Anselm, Abelard, John of Salisbury, and an anonymous epigram.

Nominalism[edit]

According to Otto of Freisingen, Roscellinus "was the first in our times to institute the theory of words",[4] but the chronicler of the "Historia Francia"[5] mentions before him a "magister Johannes", whose personality is much discussed and who has not yet been definitively identified.

The "sententia vocum" was one of the anti-realist solutions of the problem of universals accepted in the early Middle Ages. In accordance with a dichotomy set out by Porphyry,[6] the first medieval philosophers regarded genera and species either as things or as having no existence. The philosophers described this using terminology drawn from Boethius, referring to such abstract concepts as either res (things) or voces (words). Nominalists held that:

  1. only the individual exists (isres);[7]
  2. universals are merely words (voces).[8]

In Roscellinus's theory, the universal is merely an emission of sound (flatus vocis), in conformity with Boethius' definition.[9] Because Roscellinus did not discuss the philosophical concepts of genus and species, he is sometimes considered a pseudo-nominalist, or a moderate realist. However, because of his position as the first medieval philosopher to challenge medieval Realism, he has also been invoked as a forefather of modernity.[10]

Roscellinus was also taken to task by Anselm and Abelard for the less clear idea which he gave of the whole and of composite substance. According to Anselm, he maintained that colour does not exist independently of the horse which serves as its support and that the wisdom of the soul is not outside of the soul which is wise.[11] Anselm argues that Roscellinus denies to the whole, such as house, man, real existence of its parts, treating the word alone as having parts.[12]

Roscellinus was not without his supporters; among them was his contemporary Raimbert of Lille, and what the monk Hériman relates of his doctrine agrees with the statements of the master of Compiègne. Universal substances, says Hériman, are but a breath.[13] He merely comments on the saying of Anselm characterized by the same jesting tone,[14] and says that to understand the windy loquacity of Raimbert of Lille one has but to breathe into his hand.[15]

Tritheism of Roscelin[edit]

Roscelin considered the three Divine Persons as three independent beings, like three angels; if usage permitted, he added, it might truly be said that there are three Gods. Otherwise, he continued, God the Father and God the Holy Ghost would have become incarnate with God the Son. To retain the appearance of dogma he admitted that the three Divine Persons had but one will and power [Audio ... quod Roscelinus clericus dicit in tres personas esse tres res ab invicem separatas, sicut sunt tres angeli, ita tamen ut una sit voluntas et potestas aut Patrem et Spiritum sanctum esse incarnatum; et tres deos vere posse dici si usus admitteret (letter of Anselm to Foulques)].

This characteristic tritheism, which Anselm and Abelard agreed in refuting even after its author's conversion, seems an indisputable application of Roscelin's anti-Realism. He even argues that if the three Divine Persons form but one God, all three have become incarnate. There are therefore three Divine substances, three Gods, as there are three angels, because each substance constitutes an individual, which is the fundamental assertion of anti-Realism. The ideas of the theologian are closely linked with those of the philosopher.

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ Roscelin's writings and the council's acts have not survived and we know about them principally through the correspondence and writings of Anselm.[1]

References[edit]

Citations[edit]

  • ^ Russell, Bertrand. The History of Western Philosophy. Simon & Schuster, 1945, p. 436.
  • ^ ("Notices et extr. de quelques manuscr. lat.", V, Paris, 1892, 224)
  • ^ "primus nostris temporibus sententiam vocum instituit" (Gesta Friderici imp. in Monum. German. Histor.: Script., XX, 376)
  • ^ (cf. Bouquet, "Recueil des hist. des Gaules et de la France", XII, Paris, 1781, 3, b, c)
  • ^ (mox de generibus et speciebus illud quidem sive subsistent sive in nudis intellectibus posita sint)
  • ^ "nam cum habeat eorum sententia nihil esse praeter individuum ..." (De gener. et spec., 524).
  • ^ "Fuit autem, nemini magistri nostri Roscellini tam insana sententia ut nullam rem partibus constare vellet, sed sicut solis vocibus species, ita et partes ascridebat" (Abelard, Liber divisionum, ed. Cousin, 471); "[...] Illi utique dialectici, qui non nisi flatum vocis putant universalis esse substantias, et qui colorem non aliud queunt intellegere quam corpus, nec sapientiam hominis aliud quam animam, prorsus a spiritualium quaestionum disputatione sunt exsufflandi." (Anselm, De Incarnatione Verbi, p. 285. Opera Omnia, vol. 1. Ed. F.S. Schmitt, 1938); "Alius ergo consistit in vocibus, licet haec opinio cum Roscelino suo fere omnino evanuerit (John of Salisbury, Metalog., II, 17).
  • ^ "Nihil enim aliud est prolatio (vocis) quam aeris plectro linguae percussio"
  • ^ Richard J. Utz,『Medievalism as Modernism: Alfred Andersch's Nominalist Littérature engageé,』Studies in Medievalism 6 (1993), 76–90.
  • ^ (De fide trinit., 2)
  • ^ "ita divinam paginam pervertit, ut eo loco quo Dominus partem piscis assi comedisse partem hujus vocis, quae est piscis assi, non partem rei intelligere cogatur" (Cousin, P. Abaelardi opera, II. 151).
  • ^ "eos de sapientium numero merito esse exsufflandos"
  • ^ "a spiritualium quaestionum disputatione sunt exsufflandi" (P.L., 256a)
  • ^ (manuque ori admota exsufflans "Mon. Germ. Hist.", XIV, 275)
  • Bibliography[edit]


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Roscellinus&oldid=1223786973"

    Categories: 
    Philosophers of language
    1050s births
    1120s deaths
    People from Compiègne
    French male writers
    11th-century French philosophers
    11th-century French writers
    11th-century writers in Latin
    12th-century French philosophers
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Articles containing Latin-language text
    Articles incorporating a citation from the 1913 Catholic Encyclopedia without Wikisource reference
    Articles incorporating text from the 1913 Catholic Encyclopedia without Wikisource reference
    Wikipedia articles incorporating a citation from the 1911 Encyclopaedia Britannica with Wikisource reference
    Wikipedia articles incorporating text from the 1911 Encyclopædia Britannica
    Articles with Latin-language sources (la)
    Articles with FAST identifiers
    Articles with ISNI identifiers
    Articles with VIAF identifiers
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with ICCU identifiers
    Articles with J9U identifiers
    Articles with LCCN identifiers
    Articles with NKC identifiers
    Articles with NTA identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
    Articles with VcBA identifiers
    Articles with DTBIO identifiers
    Articles with SUDOC identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 14 May 2024, at 10:32 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki