Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Reasons for nonexistence  



1.1  Russell's paradox  



1.1.1  Regularity and pairing  





1.1.2  Comprehension  







1.2  Cantor's theorem  







2 Theories of universality  



2.1  Restricted comprehension  





2.2  Universal objects that are not sets  







3 See also  





4 Notes  





5 References  





6 External links  














Universal set






العربية
Беларуская
Беларуская (тарашкевіца)
Español
فارسی
Хальмг

Bahasa Indonesia
Íslenska
Italiano
Bahasa Melayu
Русский
ி
Українська
 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Inset theory, a universal set is a set which contains all objects, including itself.[1] In set theory as usually formulated, it can be proven in multiple ways that a universal set does not exist. However, some non-standard variants of set theory include a universal set.

Reasons for nonexistence[edit]

Many set theories do not allow for the existence of a universal set. There are several different arguments for its non-existence, based on different choices of axioms for set theory.

Russell's paradox[edit]

Russell's paradox concerns the impossibility of a set of sets, whose members are all sets that do not contain themselves. If such a set could exist, it could neither contain itself (because its members all do not contain themselves) nor avoid containing itself (because if it did, it should be included as one of its members).[2] This paradox prevents the existence of a universal set in set theories that include either Zermelo's axiom of restricted comprehension, or the axiom of regularity and axiom of pairing.

Regularity and pairing[edit]

InZermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the axiom of regularity and axiom of pairing prevent any set from containing itself. For any set , the set (constructed using pairing) necessarily contains an element disjoint from , by regularity. Because its only element is , it must be the case that is disjoint from , and therefore that does not contain itself. Because a universal set would necessarily contain itself, it cannot exist under these axioms.[3]

Comprehension[edit]

Russell's paradox prevents the existence of a universal set in set theories that include Zermelo's axiom of restricted comprehension. This axiom states that, for any formula and any set , there exists a set that contains exactly those elements of that satisfy .[2]

If this axiom could be applied to a universal set , with defined as the predicate , it would state the existence of Russell's paradoxical set, giving a contradiction. It was this contradiction that led the axiom of comprehension to be stated in its restricted form, where it asserts the existence of a subset of a given set rather than the existence of a set of all sets that satisfy a given formula.[2]

When the axiom of restricted comprehension is applied to an arbitrary set , with the predicate , it produces the subset of elements of that do not contain themselves. It cannot be a member of , because if it were it would be included as a member of itself, by its definition, contradicting the fact that it cannot contain itself. In this way, it is possible to construct a witness to the non-universality of , even in versions of set theory that allow sets to contain themselves. This indeed holds even with predicative comprehension and over intuitionistic logic.

Cantor's theorem[edit]

Another difficulty with the idea of a universal set concerns the power set of the set of all sets. Because this power set is a set of sets, it would necessarily be a subset of the set of all sets, provided that both exist. However, this conflicts with Cantor's theorem that the power set of any set (whether infinite or not) always has strictly higher cardinality than the set itself.

Theories of universality[edit]

The difficulties associated with a universal set can be avoided either by using a variant of set theory in which the axiom of comprehension is restricted in some way, or by using a universal object that is not considered to be a set.

Restricted comprehension[edit]

There are set theories known to be consistent (if the usual set theory is consistent) in which the universal set V does exist (and is true). In these theories, Zermelo's axiom of comprehension does not hold in general, and the axiom of comprehension of naive set theory is restricted in a different way. A set theory containing a universal set is necessarily a non-well-founded set theory. The most widely studied set theory with a universal set is Willard Van Orman Quine's New Foundations. Alonzo Church and Arnold Oberschelp also published work on such set theories. Church speculated that his theory might be extended in a manner consistent with Quine's,[4] but this is not possible for Oberschelp's, since in it the singleton function is provably a set,[5] which leads immediately to paradox in New Foundations.[6]

Another example is positive set theory, where the axiom of comprehension is restricted to hold only for the positive formulas (formulas that do not contain negations). Such set theories are motivated by notions of closure in topology.

Universal objects that are not sets[edit]

The idea of a universal set seems intuitively desirable in the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, particularly because most versions of this theory do allow the use of quantifiers over all sets (see universal quantifier). One way of allowing an object that behaves similarly to a universal set, without creating paradoxes, is to describe V and similar large collections as proper classes rather than as sets. Russell's paradox does not apply in these theories because the axiom of comprehension operates on sets, not on classes.

The category of sets can also be considered to be a universal object that is, again, not itself a set. It has all sets as elements, and also includes arrows for all functions from one set to another. Again, it does not contain itself, because it is not itself a set.

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  • ^ Cenzer et al. (2020).
  • ^ Church (1974, p. 308). See also Forster (1995, p. 136), Forster (2001, p. 17), and Sheridan (2016).
  • ^ Oberschelp (1973), p. 40.
  • ^ Holmes (1998), p. 110.
  • References[edit]

    External links[edit]

    Overview

    Venn diagram of set intersection

    Axioms

  • Choice
  • Constructibility (V=L)
  • Determinacy
  • Extensionality
  • Infinity
  • Limitation of size
  • Pairing
  • Power set
  • Regularity
  • Union
  • Martin's axiom
  • Operations

  • Complement (i.e. set difference)
  • De Morgan's laws
  • Disjoint union
  • Identities
  • Intersection
  • Power set
  • Symmetric difference
  • Union
    • Concepts
  • Methods
  • Cardinality
  • Cardinal number (large)
  • Class
  • Constructible universe
  • Continuum hypothesis
  • Diagonal argument
  • Element
  • Family
  • Forcing
  • One-to-one correspondence
  • Ordinal number
  • Set-builder notation
  • Transfinite induction
  • Venn diagram
  • Set types

  • Countable
  • Empty
  • Finite (hereditarily)
  • Filter
  • Fuzzy
  • Infinite (Dedekind-infinite)
  • Recursive
  • Singleton
  • Subset · Superset
  • Transitive
  • Uncountable
  • Universal
  • Theories

  • Axiomatic
  • Naive
  • Cantor's theorem
  • Problems
  • Suslin's problem
  • Burali-Forti paradox
  • Set theorists

  • Georg Cantor
  • Paul Cohen
  • Richard Dedekind
  • Abraham Fraenkel
  • Kurt Gödel
  • Thomas Jech
  • John von Neumann
  • Willard Quine
  • Bertrand Russell
  • Thoralf Skolem
  • Ernst Zermelo
  • General

  • Cardinality
  • First-order logic
  • Formal proof
  • Formal semantics
  • Foundations of mathematics
  • Information theory
  • Lemma
  • Logical consequence
  • Model
  • Theorem
  • Theory
  • Type theory
  • Theorems (list)
     and paradoxes

  • Tarski's undefinability
  • Banach–Tarski paradox
  • Cantor's theorem, paradox and diagonal argument
  • Compactness
  • Halting problem
  • Lindström's
  • Löwenheim–Skolem
  • Russell's paradox
  • Logics

    Traditional

  • Logical truth
  • Tautology
  • Proposition
  • Inference
  • Logical equivalence
  • Consistency
  • Argument
  • Soundness
  • Validity
  • Syllogism
  • Square of opposition
  • Venn diagram
  • Propositional

  • Boolean functions
  • Logical connectives
  • Propositional calculus
  • Propositional formula
  • Truth tables
  • Many-valued logic
  • Predicate

  • Second-order
  • Higher-order
  • Fixed-point
  • Free
  • Quantifiers
  • Predicate
  • Monadic predicate calculus
  • Set theory

  • Class
  • (Ur-)Element
  • Ordinal number
  • Extensionality
  • Forcing
  • Relation
  • Set operations:
  • Types of sets

  • Uncountable
  • Empty
  • Inhabited
  • Singleton
  • Finite
  • Infinite
  • Transitive
  • Ultrafilter
  • Recursive
  • Fuzzy
  • Universal
  • Universe
  • Maps and cardinality

  • codomain
  • image
  • In/Sur/Bi-jection
  • Schröder–Bernstein theorem
  • Isomorphism
  • Gödel numbering
  • Enumeration
  • Large cardinal
  • Aleph number
  • Operation
  • Set theories

  • continuum hypothesis
  • General
  • Kripke–Platek
  • Morse–Kelley
  • Naive
  • New Foundations
  • Tarski–Grothendieck
  • Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel
  • Ackermann
  • Constructive
  • Formal systems (list),
    language and syntax

  • Arity
  • Automata
  • Axiom schema
  • Expression
  • Extension
  • Relation
  • Formation rule
  • Grammar
  • Formula
  • Free/bound variable
  • Language
  • Metalanguage
  • Logical connective
  • Predicate
  • Proof
  • Quantifier
  • Sentence
  • Signature
  • String
  • Substitution
  • Symbol
  • Term
  • Theory
  • Example axiomatic
    systems
     (list)

  • second-order
  • elementary function
  • primitive recursive
  • Robinson
  • Skolem
  • of the real numbers
  • ofBoolean algebras
  • ofgeometry:
  • Proof theory

  • Natural deduction
  • Logical consequence
  • Rule of inference
  • Sequent calculus
  • Theorem
  • Systems
  • Complete theory
  • Independence (from ZFC)
  • Proof of impossibility
  • Ordinal analysis
  • Reverse mathematics
  • Self-verifying theories
  • Model theory

  • of models
  • Model
  • Non-standard model
  • Diagram
  • Categorical theory
  • Model complete theory
  • Satisfiability
  • Semantics of logic
  • Strength
  • Theories of truth
  • T-schema
  • Transfer principle
  • Truth predicate
  • Truth value
  • Type
  • Ultraproduct
  • Validity
  • Computability theory

  • Church–Turing thesis
  • Computably enumerable
  • Computable function
  • Computable set
  • Decision problem
  • Kolmogorov complexity
  • Lambda calculus
  • Primitive recursive function
  • Recursion
  • Recursive set
  • Turing machine
  • Type theory
  • Related

  • Algebraic logic
  • Automated theorem proving
  • Category theory
  • Concrete/Abstract category
  • Category of sets
  • History of logic
  • History of mathematical logic
  • Logicism
  • Mathematical object
  • Philosophy of mathematics
  • Supertask
  • icon Mathematics portal


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Universal_set&oldid=1224910068"

    Categories: 
    Basic concepts in set theory
    Families of sets
    Paradoxes of naive set theory
    Systems of set theory
    Wellfoundedness
    Self-reference
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
     



    This page was last edited on 21 May 2024, at 06:43 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki