Home  

Random  

Nearby  



Log in  



Settings  



Donate  



About Wikipedia  

Disclaimers  



Wikipedia





Arcesilaus





Article  

Talk  



Language  

Watch  

Edit  





Arcesilaus (/ˌɑːrsɛsɪˈl.əs/; Greek: Ἀρκεσίλαος; 316/5–241/0 BC)[1] was a Greek Hellenistic philosopher. He was the founder of Academic Skepticism and what is variously called the Second or Middle or New Academy – the phase of the Platonic Academy in which it embraced philosophical skepticism.

Arcesilaus
Arcesilaus and Carneades
Born316/5 BC
Died241/0 BC
Athens
(modern-day Greece)
EraHellenistic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAcademic Skepticism

Main interests

Epistemology

Notable ideas

Founder of Academic Skepticism

Arcesilaus succeeded Crates of Athens as the sixth scholarch of the academy around 264 BC.[2] He did not preserve his thoughts in writing, so his opinions can only be gleaned second-hand from what is preserved by later writers.

In Athens Arcesilaus interacted with the Pyrrhonist philosopher, Timon of Phlius,[3] whose philosophy appears to have influenced Arcesilaus to become the first Academic to adopt a position of philosophical skepticism, that is, he doubted the ability of the senses to discover truth about the world, although he may have continued to believe in the existence of truth itself. This brought in the skeptical phase of the academy. His chief opponent was his contemporary, Zeno of Citium, the founder of Stoicism, whose dogmaofkatalepsis (i.e., that reality could be comprehended with certainty) Arcesilaus denied.

Life

edit

Arcesilaus was born in PitaneinAeolis. His early education was provided by Autolycus the mathematician, with whom he migrated to Sardis. Afterwards, he studied rhetoricinAthens. He then studied philosophy, becoming a disciple first of Theophrastus and afterwards of Crantor.[4] He also attended the school of Pyrrho, whose philosophy he maintained, except in name.[5] He subsequently became intimate with Polemo and Crates of Athens, who made Arcesilaus his successor as scholarch (head) of the Platonic Academy. [6]

Diogenes Laërtius says that, like his successor Lacydes, Arcesilaus died of excessive drinking, but the testimony of others (e.g. Cleanthes, who said that he lived a dutiful life) and his own precepts discredit the story.[7] He is known to have been much respected by the Athenians.[6]

Philosophy

edit

Arcesilaus committed nothing to writing. His opinions were imperfectly known to his contemporaries, and can now only be gathered from the statements of later writers. This makes his philosophy difficult to evaluate and partly inconsistent. This led scholars to see his skepticism in several ways. Some see his philosophy as completely negative or destructive of all philosophical views. Others regard him as taking the position that nothing can be known on the basis of his philosophical arguments. Others claimed he held no positive views on any philosophical topic, including the possibility of knowledge.[8]

Arcesilaus' contemporary, Aristo of Chios, described Arcesilaus as being: "Plato the head of him, Pyrrho the tail, midway Diodorus"[9] meaning that Arcesilaus presented himself as a Platonist, the substance of what he taught was the dialectics of Diodorus, but his actual philosophy was that of Pyrrhonism.[10] Eusebius, probably quoting Aristocles of Messene, reported that Arcesilaus studied in Pyrrho's school and adhered, except in name, to Pyrrhonism.[11] Numenius of Apamea said "Arcesilaus accompanied Pyrrho. He remained Pyrrhonist in his rejection of everything, except in name. At least the Pyrrhonists Mnaseas, Philomelos and Timon call him a Pyrrhonist, just as they were themselves, because he too rejected the true, the false, and the persuasive."[12] Sextus Empiricus said that Arcesilaus' philosophy appeared essentially the same as Pyrrhonism, but granted that this might have been superficial.[13]

On the one hand, Arcesilaus professed to be no innovator, but a reviver of the dogma-free dialectic that had characterized the academy under Plato.[14] Thus he is said to have restored the doctrines of Plato in an uncorrupted form. On the other hand, according to Cicero,[15] he summed up his opinions in the formula, "that he knew nothing, not even his own ignorance." There are two ways of reconciling the difficulty: either we may suppose him to have thrown out such aphorisms as an exercise for his pupils, as Sextus Empiricus,[16] who calls him a "skeptic", would have us believe; or he may have really doubted the esoteric meaning of Plato, and have supposed himself to have been stripping his works of the figments of the Dogmatists, while he was in fact taking from them all certain principles.[17]

Cicero attributes the following argument to Arcesilaus:

(i) it is rash and shameful to assent to something false or unknown, but since (ii) nothing can be known (and obviously we shouldn't do what is rash and shameful), (iii) we should suspend judgment about everything[18]

Zeno of Citium and the other Stoics were the chief opponents of Arcesilaus. He attacked their dogmaofkatalêptikê phantasia (i.e., a convincing conception) as understood to be a mean between episteme (knowledge) and doxa (opinion). He argued that this mean could not exist. It involved a contradiction in terms, as the very idea of phantasia implied the possibility of false as well as true conceptions of the same object. As such, it was merely the interpolation of a name.[19]

Commentary on Arcesilaus

edit

The Pyrrhonist philosopher and contemporary of Arcesilaus, Timon of Phlius ridiculed Arcesilaus in his Silloi, but also praised him in Funeral Banquet of Arcesilaus.[3] Fragments from Timon about Arcesilaus include:

Blaise Pascal wrote of Arcesilaus in his Pensées (1669, para. 375):

I have seen changes in all nations and men, and thus after many changes of judgement regarding true justice, I have recognized that our nature was but in continual change, and I have not changed since; and if I changed, I would confirm my opinion. The skeptic Arcesilaus, who became a dogmatist.

Notes

edit
  1. ^ Dorandi 1999, p. 48.
  • ^ "Arcesilaus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 31 March 2016.
  • ^ a b Diogenes Laërtius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Book IX, Chapter 12, Section 114–115 [1]
  • ^ Eusebius of Caesarea: Praeparatio EvangelicaVI
  • ^ Eusebius of Caesarea, Praeparatio Evangelica Chapter VI
  • ^ a b Chisholm 1911.
  • ^ Holiday, Ryan; Hanselman, Stephen (2020). Lives of the Stoics: The Art of Living from Zeno to Marcus Aurelius. Profile. p. 21. ISBN 978-1782835509.
  • ^ "Arcesilaus (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". Plato.stanford.edu. 2005-01-14. Retrieved 31 March 2016.
  • ^ Laërtius 1925b, § 35; and Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism.
  • ^ "Arcesilaus ... does indeed seem to me to share the Pyrrhonean arguments, so that his Way is almost the same as ours.... he made use of the dialectic of Diodorus, but he was an outwardly Platonist." Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I, Chapter 33.
  • ^ Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica Chapter VI
  • ^ Numenius, fr. 25.64–71
  • ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, Book 1, Chapter 33, Section 232
  • ^ David Sedley, in Doubt and Dogmatism Oxford University Press, 1980, p. 11
  • ^ Cicero, Academica, i. 12
  • ^ Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrh. Hypotyp. i. 234
  • ^ Cicero, De Oratore, iii. 18.
  • ^ Cicero Academica Varro, 44–45
  • ^ Cicero, Academica, ii. 24.
  • ^ Diogenes Laërtius Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Book IV, Chapter 6, Section 33 [2]
  • Sources

    edit

    Attribution

    edit
    edit

    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Arcesilaus&oldid=1200580045"
     



    Last edited on 29 January 2024, at 20:42  





    Languages

     


    العربية
    Български
    Català
    Čeština
    Deutsch
    Ελληνικά
    Español
    Esperanto
    Euskara
    Français

    Հայերեն
    Hrvatski
    Bahasa Indonesia
    Íslenska
    Italiano
    עברית

    Қазақша
    Кыргызча
    Latina
    Magyar
    مصرى
    Nederlands

    Norsk bokmål
    پښتو
    Polski
    Português
    Русский
    Slovenčina
    Slovenščina
    Српски / srpski
    Srpskohrvatski / српскохрватски
    Suomi
    Svenska
    ி
    Türkçe
    Українська

     

    Wikipedia


    This page was last edited on 29 January 2024, at 20:42 (UTC).

    Content is available under CC BY-SA 4.0 unless otherwise noted.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Terms of Use

    Desktop