Home  

Random  

Nearby  



Log in  



Settings  



Donate  



About Wikipedia  

Disclaimers  



Wikipedia





Equivalence relation





Article  

Talk  



Language  

Watch  

Edit  





Transitive binary relations
  • t
  • e
  • Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
    Total, Semiconnex Anti-
    reflexive
    Equivalence relation Green tickY Green tickY
    Preorder (Quasiorder) Green tickY
    Partial order Green tickY Green tickY
    Total preorder Green tickY Green tickY
    Total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Prewellordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Well-quasi-ordering Green tickY Green tickY
    Well-ordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Lattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Join-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Meet-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict partial order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict weak order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Strict total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
    Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
    Definitions, for all and
    Green tickY indicates that the column's property is always true the row's term (at the very left), while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general (it might, or might not, hold). For example, that every equivalence relation is symmetric, but not necessarily antisymmetric, is indicated by Green tickY in the "Symmetric" column and in the "Antisymmetric" column, respectively.

    All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation betransitive: for all if and then
    A term's definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table.

    Inmathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equality. Any number is equal to itself (reflexive). If , then (symmetric). If and , then (transitive).

    The 52 equivalence relations on a 5-element set depicted as logical matrices (colored fields, including those in light gray, stand for ones; white fields for zeros). The row and column indices of nonwhite cells are the related elements, while the different colors, other than light gray, indicate the equivalence classes (each light gray cell is its own equivalence class).

    Each equivalence relation provides a partition of the underlying set into disjoint equivalence classes. Two elements of the given set are equivalent to each other if and only if they belong to the same equivalence class.

    Notation

    edit

    Various notations are used in the literature to denote that two elements   and   of a set are equivalent with respect to an equivalence relation   the most common are " " and "ab", which are used when   is implicit, and variations of " ", "aR b", or " " to specify   explicitly. Non-equivalence may be written "ab" or " ".

    Definition

    edit

    Abinary relation   on a set   is said to be an equivalence relation, if and only if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. That is, for all   and  in 

      together with the relation   is called a setoid. The equivalence classof  under   denoted   is defined as  [1][2]

    Alternative definition using relational algebra

    edit

    Inrelational algebra, if   and   are relations, then the composite relation   is defined so that   if and only if there is a   such that   and  .[note 1] This definition is a generalisation of the definition of functional composition. The defining properties of an equivalence relation   on a set   can then be reformulated as follows:

    Examples

    edit

    Simple example

    edit

    On the set  , the relation   is an equivalence relation. The following sets are equivalence classes of this relation:  

    The set of all equivalence classes for  is  This set is a partition of the set   with respect to  .

    Equivalence relations

    edit

    The following relations are all equivalence relations:

    Relations that are not equivalences

    edit

    Connections to other relations

    edit

    Well-definedness under an equivalence relation

    edit

    If  is an equivalence relation on   and   is a property of elements of   such that whenever     is true if   is true, then the property   is said to be well-defined or a class invariant under the relation  

    A frequent particular case occurs when   is a function from   to another set  if  implies   then   is said to be a morphism for  aclass invariant under   or simply invariant under   This occurs, e.g. in the character theory of finite groups. The latter case with the function   can be expressed by a commutative triangle. See also invariant. Some authors use "compatible with  " or just "respects  " instead of "invariant under  ".

    More generally, a function may map equivalent arguments (under an equivalence relation  ) to equivalent values (under an equivalence relation  ). Such a function is known as a morphism from  to 

    edit

    Let  , and   be an equivalence relation. Some key definitions and terminology follow:

    Equivalence class

    edit

    A subset  of  such that   holds for all   and  in , and never for  in  and   outside  , is called an equivalence classof by . Let   denote the equivalence class to which   belongs. All elements of   equivalent to each other are also elements of the same equivalence class.

    Quotient set

    edit

    The set of all equivalence classes of  by  denoted   is the quotient setof by If  is a topological space, there is a natural way of transforming   into a topological space; see Quotient space for the details.

    Projection

    edit

    The projectionof  is the function   defined by   which maps elements of   into their respective equivalence classes by  

    Theoremonprojections:[4] Let the function   be such that if   then   Then there is a unique function   such that  If  is a surjection and   then   is a bijection.

    Equivalence kernel

    edit

    The equivalence kernel of a function   is the equivalence relation ~ defined by   The equivalence kernel of an injection is the identity relation.

    Partition

    edit

    ApartitionofX is a set P of nonempty subsets of X, such that every element of X is an element of a single element of P. Each element of P is a cell of the partition. Moreover, the elements of P are pairwise disjoint and their unionisX.

    Counting partitions

    edit

    Let X be a finite set with n elements. Since every equivalence relation over X corresponds to a partition of X, and vice versa, the number of equivalence relations on X equals the number of distinct partitions of X, which is the nthBell number Bn:

      (Dobinski's formula).

    Fundamental theorem of equivalence relations

    edit

    A key result links equivalence relations and partitions:[5][6][7]

    In both cases, the cells of the partition of X are the equivalence classes of X by ~. Since each element of X belongs to a unique cell of any partition of X, and since each cell of the partition is identical to an equivalence class of X by ~, each element of X belongs to a unique equivalence class of X by ~. Thus there is a natural bijection between the set of all equivalence relations on X and the set of all partitions of X.

    Comparing equivalence relations

    edit

    If  and   are two equivalence relations on the same set  , and   implies   for all   then   is said to be a coarser relation than  , and   is a finer relation than  . Equivalently,

    The equality equivalence relation is the finest equivalence relation on any set, while the universal relation, which relates all pairs of elements, is the coarsest.

    The relation "  is finer than  " on the collection of all equivalence relations on a fixed set is itself a partial order relation, which makes the collection a geometric lattice.[8]

    Generating equivalence relations

    edit
      if there exists a natural number   and elements   such that  ,  , and  or , for  
    The equivalence relation generated in this manner can be trivial. For instance, the equivalence relation generated by any total orderonX has exactly one equivalence class, X itself.

    Algebraic structure

    edit

    Much of mathematics is grounded in the study of equivalences, and order relations. Lattice theory captures the mathematical structure of order relations. Even though equivalence relations are as ubiquitous in mathematics as order relations, the algebraic structure of equivalences is not as well known as that of orders. The former structure draws primarily on group theory and, to a lesser extent, on the theory of lattices, categories, and groupoids.

    Group theory

    edit

    Just as order relations are grounded in ordered sets, sets closed under pairwise supremum and infimum, equivalence relations are grounded in partitioned sets, which are sets closed under bijections that preserve partition structure. Since all such bijections map an equivalence class onto itself, such bijections are also known as permutations. Hence permutation groups (also known as transformation groups) and the related notion of orbit shed light on the mathematical structure of equivalence relations.

    Let '~' denote an equivalence relation over some nonempty set A, called the universe or underlying set. Let G denote the set of bijective functions over A that preserve the partition structure of A, meaning that for all   and   Then the following three connected theorems hold:[10]

    In sum, given an equivalence relation ~ over A, there exists a transformation group G over A whose orbits are the equivalence classes of A under ~.

    This transformation group characterisation of equivalence relations differs fundamentally from the way lattices characterize order relations. The arguments of the lattice theory operations meet and join are elements of some universe A. Meanwhile, the arguments of the transformation group operations composition and inverse are elements of a set of bijections, AA.

    Moving to groups in general, let H be a subgroup of some group G. Let ~ be an equivalence relation on G, such that   The equivalence classes of ~—also called the orbits of the actionofHonG—are the right cosetsofHinG. Interchanging a and b yields the left cosets.

    Related thinking can be found in Rosen (2008: chpt. 10).

    Categories and groupoids

    edit

    Let G be a set and let "~" denote an equivalence relation over G. Then we can form a groupoid representing this equivalence relation as follows. The objects are the elements of G, and for any two elements x and yofG, there exists a unique morphism from xtoy if and only if  

    The advantages of regarding an equivalence relation as a special case of a groupoid include:

    Lattices

    edit

    The equivalence relations on any set X, when ordered by set inclusion, form a complete lattice, called Con X by convention. The canonical map ker : X^XCon X, relates the monoid X^X of all functionsonX and Con X. kerissurjective but not injective. Less formally, the equivalence relation keronX, takes each function f : XX to its kernel ker f. Likewise, ker(ker) is an equivalence relation on X^X.

    Equivalence relations and mathematical logic

    edit

    Equivalence relations are a ready source of examples or counterexamples. For example, an equivalence relation with exactly two infinite equivalence classes is an easy example of a theory which is ω-categorical, but not categorical for any larger cardinal number.

    An implication of model theory is that the properties defining a relation can be proved independent of each other (and hence necessary parts of the definition) if and only if, for each property, examples can be found of relations not satisfying the given property while satisfying all the other properties. Hence the three defining properties of equivalence relations can be proved mutually independent by the following three examples:

    Properties definable in first-order logic that an equivalence relation may or may not possess include:

    See also

    edit

    Notes

    edit
    1. ^ Sometimes the composition   is instead written as  , or as  ; in both cases,   is the first relation that is applied. See the article on Composition of relations for more information.
    1. ^ If: Given   let   hold using totality, then   by symmetry, hence   by transitivity. — Only if: Given   choose   then   by reflexivity.
    1. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Equivalence Class". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-30.
  • ^ a b c "7.3: Equivalence Classes". Mathematics LibreTexts. 2017-09-20. Retrieved 2020-08-30.
  • ^ Halmos, Paul Richard (1914). Naive Set Theory. New York: Springer. p. 41. ISBN 978-0-387-90104-6.
  • ^ Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane, 1999 (1967). Algebra, 3rd ed. p. 35, Th. 19. Chelsea.
  • ^ Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. p. 31, Th. 8. Springer-Verlag.
  • ^ Dummit, D. S., and Foote, R. M., 2004. Abstract Algebra, 3rd ed. p. 3, Prop. 2. John Wiley & Sons.
  • ^ Karel Hrbacek & Thomas Jech (1999) Introduction to Set Theory, 3rd edition, pages 29–32, Marcel Dekker
  • ^ Birkhoff, Garrett (1995), Lattice Theory, Colloquium Publications, vol. 25 (3rd ed.), American Mathematical Society, ISBN 9780821810255. Sect. IV.9, Theorem 12, page 95
  • ^ Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane, 1999 (1967). Algebra, 3rd ed. p. 33, Th. 18. Chelsea.
  • ^ Rosen (2008), pp. 243–45. Less clear is §10.3 of Bas van Fraassen, 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford Univ. Press.
  • ^ Bas van Fraassen, 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford Univ. Press: 246.
  • ^ Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. Springer-Verlag: 22, Th. 6.
  • ^ Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. Springer-Verlag: 24, Th. 7.
  • ^ Proof.[11] Let function composition interpret group multiplication, and function inverse interpret group inverse. Then G is a group under composition, meaning that   and   because G satisfies the following four conditions: Let f and g be any two elements of G. By virtue of the definition of G, [g(f(x))] = [f(x)] and [f(x)] = [x], so that [g(f(x))] = [x]. Hence G is also a transformation group (and an automorphism group) because function composition preserves the partitioning of  
  • ^ Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. Springer-Verlag: 202, Th. 6.
  • ^ Dummit, D. S., and Foote, R. M., 2004. Abstract Algebra, 3rd ed. John Wiley & Sons: 114, Prop. 2.
  • ^ Borceux, F. and Janelidze, G., 2001. Galois theories, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-80309-8
  • References

    edit
    edit

    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Equivalence_relation&oldid=1198625352"
     



    Last edited on 24 January 2024, at 16:31  





    Languages

     


    العربية
    Asturianu

    Башҡортса
    Bosanski
    Català
    Čeština
    Dansk
    Deutsch
    Eesti
    Ελληνικά
    Español
    Esperanto
    Euskara
    فارسی
    Français
    Galego

    ि
    Hrvatski
    Bahasa Indonesia
    Interlingua
    Íslenska
    Italiano
    עברית

    Latina
    Lombard
    Magyar
    Nederlands

    Norsk bokmål
    Norsk nynorsk
    Occitan
    Piemontèis
    Polski
    Português
    Română
    Русский
    Shqip
    Simple English
    Slovenčina
    Slovenščina
    Српски / srpski
    Suomi
    Svenska
    ி
    Türkçe
    Українська
    اردو
    Tiếng Vit



     

    Wikipedia


    This page was last edited on 24 January 2024, at 16:31 (UTC).

    Content is available under CC BY-SA 4.0 unless otherwise noted.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Terms of Use

    Desktop