Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Life and career  





2 Philosophical work  



2.1  Induction and "grue"  





2.2  Nominalism and mereology  







3 Select bibliography  





4 See also  





5 Notes  





6 References  





7 External links  














Nelson Goodman






العربية
Català
Čeština
Dansk
Deutsch
Eesti
Ελληνικά
Español
Euskara
فارسی
Français

Հայերեն
Bahasa Indonesia
Íslenska
Italiano
עברית
Кыргызча
Nederlands

Piemontèis
Polski
Português
Русский
Slovenčina
Slovenščina
Српски / srpski
Suomi
Svenska
Türkçe

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Nelson Goodman
Born

Henry Nelson Goodman


August 7, 1906
DiedNovember 25, 1998(1998-11-25) (aged 92)
EducationHarvard University (PhD, 1941)
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic
Nominalism[1]
ThesisA Study of Qualities (1941)
Doctoral advisorC. I. Lewis
Doctoral studentsIsrael Scheffler
Other notable studentsNoam Chomsky, Sydney Morgenbesser, Stephen Stich, Hilary Putnam

Main interests

Logic, induction, counterfactuals, mereology, aesthetics, philosophy of science, philosophy of language

Notable ideas

New riddle of induction, Goodman–Leonard calculus of individuals,[1] counterfactual conditional, Goodman's method, languages of art, irrealism

Henry Nelson Goodman (7 August 1906 – 25 November 1998) was an American philosopher, known for his work on counterfactuals, mereology, the problem of induction, irrealism, and aesthetics.

Life and career[edit]

Goodman was born in Somerville, Massachusetts, the son of Sarah Elizabeth (née Woodbury) and Henry Lewis Goodman.[3] He was of Jewish origins.[4] He graduated from Harvard University, AB, magna cum laude (1928). During the 1930s, he ran an art galleryinBoston, Massachusetts, while studying for a Harvard PhDinphilosophy, which he completed in 1941.[5] His experience as an art dealer helps explain his later turn towards aesthetics, where he became better known than in logic and analytic philosophy. During World War II, he served as a psychologist in the US Army.[6]

He taught at the University of Pennsylvania, 1946–1964, where his students included Noam Chomsky, Sydney Morgenbesser, Stephen Stich, and Hilary Putnam. He was a research fellow at the Harvard Center for Cognitive Studies from 1962 to 1963 and was a professor at Brandeis University from 1964 to 1967, before being appointed Professor of Philosophy at Harvard in 1968.[7]

In 1967, at the Harvard Graduate School of Education, he was the founding director of Harvard Project Zero, a basic research project in artistic cognition and artistic education. He remained the director for four years and served as an informal adviser for many years thereafter.[8]

Goodman died in Needham, Massachusetts.

Philosophical work[edit]

Induction and "grue"[edit]

In his book Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, Goodman introduced the "new riddle of induction", so-called by analogy with Hume's classical problem of induction. He accepted Hume's observation that inductive reasoning (i.e. inferring from past experience about events in the future) was based solely on human habit and regularities to which our day-to-day existence has accustomed us. Goodman argued, however, that Hume overlooked the fact that some regularities establish habits (a given piece of copper conducting electricity increases the credibility of statements asserting that other pieces of copper conduct electricity) while some do not (the fact that a given man in a room is a third son does not increase the credibility of statements asserting that other men in this room are third sons).

Hempel's confirmation theory argued that the solution is to differentiate between hypotheses, which apply to all things of a certain class, and evidence statements, which apply to only one thing. Goodman's famous counterargument was to introduce the predicate grue, which applies to all things examined before a certain time t just in case they are green, but also to other things just in case they are blue and not examined before time t. If we examine emeralds before time t and find that emerald a is green, emerald b is green, and so forth, each will confirm the hypothesis that all emeralds are green. However, emeralds a, b, c,..etc. also confirm the hypothesis that all emeralds are grue. Thus, before time t, the apparently law-like statements "All emeralds are green" and "All emeralds are grue" are equally well confirmed by observation, but obviously "All emeralds are grue" is not a law-like statement.

Goodman's example showed that the difficulty in determining what constitutes law-like statements is far greater than previously thought, and that once again we find ourselves facing the initial dilemma that "anything can confirm anything".

Nominalism and mereology[edit]

Goodman, along with Stanislaw Lesniewski, is the founder of the contemporary variant of nominalism, which argues that philosophy, logic, and mathematics should dispense with set theory. Goodman's nominalism was driven purely by ontological considerations. After a long and difficult 1947 paper coauthored with W. V. O. Quine, Goodman ceased to trouble himself with finding a way to reconstruct mathematics while dispensing with set theory – discredited as sole foundations of mathematics as of 1913 (Russell and Whitehead, in Principia Mathematica).

The program of David Hilbert to reconstruct it from logical axioms was proven futile in 1931 by Gödel. Because of this and other failures of seemingly fruitful lines of research, Quine soon came to believe that such a reconstruction was impossible, but Goodman's Penn colleague Richard Milton Martin argued otherwise, writing a number of papers suggesting ways forward.

According to Thomas Tymoczko's afterwordinNew directions in the philosophy of mathematics, Quine had "urged that we abandon ad hoc devices distinguishing mathematics from science and just accept the resulting assimilation", putting the "key burden on the theories (networks of sentences) that we accept, not on the individual sentences whose significance can change dramatically depending on their theoretical context." In so doing, Tymoczko claimed, philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of science were merged into quasi-empiricism: the emphasis of mathematical practice as effectively part of the scientific method, an emphasis on method over result.

The Goodman–Leonard (1940) calculus of individuals is the starting point for the American variant of mereology. While the exposition in Goodman and Leonard invoked a bit of naive set theory, the variant of the calculus of individuals that grounds Goodman's 1951 The Structure of Appearance, a revision and extension of his PhD thesis, makes no mention of the notion of set (while his PhD thesis still did).[9] Simons (1987) and Casati and Varzi (1999) show that the calculus of individuals can be grounded in either a bit of set theory, or monadic predicates, schematically employed. Mereology is accordingly "ontologically neutral" and retains some of Quine's pragmatism (which Tymoczko in 1998 carefully qualified as American Pragmatism).

Select bibliography[edit]

Source: Complete International Bibliography[12]

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  • ^ Hunter, Bruce, 2016 "Clarence Irving Lewis" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • ^ John K. Roth, Christina J. Moose, Rowena Wildin (eds.), World Philosophers and Their Works: Freud, Sigmund – Oakeshott, Michael, Salem Press, 2000, p. 735.
  • ^ Daniel Cohnitz & Marcus Rossberg, Nelson Goodman, Routledge (2014), p. 6
  • ^ "Goodman Dies". Harvard University Gazette. Archived from the original on 14 June 2013. Retrieved 18 January 2014.
  • ^ Gardner, Howard (2000). "Project Zero: Nelson Goodman's Legacy in Arts Education". The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 58 (3): 245–249. doi:10.2307/432107. ISSN 0021-8529. JSTOR 432107.
  • ^ Cohnitz, Daniel; Rossberg, Marcus (2022), "Nelson Goodman", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2023-06-05
  • ^ Gardner, H., and Perkins, D. "The Mark of Zero: Project Zero's Identity Revealed." HGSE Alumni Bulletin, December 1994, 39(1), 2–6.
  • ^ Cohnitz and Rossberg (2003), ch. 5
  • ^ Wertheimer, Roger (July 1972). "Review of Problems and Projects by Nelson Goodman". Commentary.
  • ^ Nehamas, Alexander (1984). "Review of Of Mind and Other Matters by Nelson Goodman". The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. 43 (2). JSTOR: 209–211. doi:10.2307/429995. ISSN 0021-8529. JSTOR 429995.
  • ^ "An International Bibliography of Works by and Selected Works about Nelson Goodman". homepages.inf.ed.ac.uk. Retrieved 2019-09-17.
  • References[edit]

    External links[edit]


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Nelson_Goodman&oldid=1218554729"

    Categories: 
    1906 births
    1998 deaths
    20th-century American non-fiction writers
    20th-century American philosophers
    20th-century American essayists
    American male essayists
    American male non-fiction writers
    American philosophy academics
    Analytic philosophers
    American epistemologists
    Harvard Graduate School of Arts and Sciences alumni
    Harvard University Department of Philosophy faculty
    Jewish American military personnel
    Jewish philosophers
    Ontologists
    People from Needham, Massachusetts
    People from Somerville, Massachusetts
    American philosophers of art
    American philosophers of language
    American philosophers of logic
    American philosophers of mathematics
    American philosophers of mind
    American philosophers of social science
    Philosophy writers
    University of Pennsylvania faculty
    20th-century American male writers
    Corresponding Fellows of the British Academy
    20th-century American Jews
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Pages using infobox philosopher with unknown parameters
    Articles with hCards
    Articles with FAST identifiers
    Articles with ISNI identifiers
    Articles with VIAF identifiers
    Articles with WorldCat Entities identifiers
    Articles with BIBSYS identifiers
    Articles with BNE identifiers
    Articles with BNF identifiers
    Articles with BNFdata identifiers
    Articles with CANTICN identifiers
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with ICCU identifiers
    Articles with J9U identifiers
    Articles with KBR identifiers
    Articles with LCCN identifiers
    Articles with Libris identifiers
    Articles with LNB identifiers
    Articles with NDL identifiers
    Articles with NKC identifiers
    Articles with NLG identifiers
    Articles with NSK identifiers
    Articles with NTA identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
    Articles with PortugalA identifiers
    Articles with CINII identifiers
    Articles with DBLP identifiers
    Articles with ULAN identifiers
    Articles with DTBIO identifiers
    Articles with SNAC-ID identifiers
    Articles with SUDOC identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 12 April 2024, at 12:05 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki