Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Introduction  



1.1  The Physical process of computation  







2 Alternative accounts of computation  



2.1  The mapping account  





2.2  The semantic account  





2.3  The mechanistic account  







3 Mathematical models  





4 See also  





5 Notes  





6 References  














Computation






العربية


 / Bân-lâm-gú
Ελληνικά
Euskara
فارسی
Galego

Հայերեն
Hrvatski
IsiZulu
Italiano
עברית
Bahasa Melayu
Mirandés
Монгол
Simple English
کوردی
Српски / srpski
Sunda
Suomi
Tagalog
ி

Türkçe
Українська
Tiếng Vit

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Acomputation is any type of arithmetic or non-arithmetic calculation that is well-defined.[1][2] Common examples of computation are mathematical equation solving and the execution of computer algorithms.

Mechanical or electronic devices (or, historically, people) that perform computations are known as computers. Computer science is a field that involves the study of computation.

Introduction[edit]

The notion that mathematical statements should be 'well-defined' had been argued by mathematicians since at least the 1600s,[3] but agreement on a suitable definition proved elusive.[4] A candidate definition was proposed independently by several mathematicians in the 1930s.[5] The best-known variant was formalised by the mathematician Alan Turing, who defined a well-defined statement or calculation as any statement that could be expressed in terms of the initialisation parameters of a Turing machine.[6] Other (mathematically equivalent) definitions include Alonzo Church's lambda-definability, Herbrand-Gödel-Kleene's general recursiveness and Emil Post's 1-definability.[5]

Today, any formal statement or calculation that exhibits this quality of well-definedness is termed computable, while the statement or calculation itself is referred to as a computation.

Turing's definition apportioned "well-definedness" to a very large class of mathematical statements, including all well-formed algebraic statements, and all statements written in modern computer programming languages.[7]

Despite the widespread uptake of this definition, there are some mathematical concepts that have no well-defined characterisation under this definition. This includes the halting problem and the busy beaver game. It remains an open question as to whether there exists a more powerful definition of 'well-defined' that is able to capture both computable and 'non-computable' statements.[note 1][8]

Some examples of mathematical statements that are computable include:

Some examples of mathematical statements that are not computable include:

The Physical process of computation[edit]

Computation can be seen as a purely physical process occurring inside a closed physical system called a computer. Turing's 1937 proof, On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem, demonstrated that there is a formal equivalence between computable statements and particular physical systems, commonly called computers. Examples of such physical systems are: Turing machines, human mathematicians following strict rules, digital computers, mechanical computers, analog computers and others.

Alternative accounts of computation[edit]

The mapping account[edit]

An alternative account of computation is found throughout the works of Hilary Putnam and others. Peter Godfrey-Smith has dubbed this the "simple mapping account."[9] Gualtiero Piccinini's summary of this account states that a physical system can be said to perform a specific computation when there is a mapping between the state of that system and the computation such that the "microphysical states [of the system] mirror the state transitions between the computational states."[10]

The semantic account[edit]

Philosophers such as Jerry Fodor[11] have suggested various accounts of computation with the restriction that semantic content be a necessary condition for computation (that is, what differentiates an arbitrary physical system from a computing system is that the operands of the computation represent something). This notion attempts to prevent the logical abstraction of the mapping account of pancomputationalism, the idea that everything can be said to be computing everything.

The mechanistic account[edit]

Gualtiero Piccinini proposes an account of computation based on mechanical philosophy. It states that physical computing systems are types of mechanisms that, by design, perform physical computation, or the manipulation (by a functional mechanism) of a "medium-independent" vehicle according to a rule. "Medium-independence" requires that the property can be instantiated[clarification needed] by multiple realizers[clarification needed] and multiple mechanisms, and that the inputs and outputs of the mechanism also be multiply realizable. In short, medium-independence allows for the use of physical variables with properties other than voltage (as in typical digital computers); this is imperative in considering other types of computation, such as that which occurs in the brain or in a quantum computer. A rule, in this sense, provides a mapping among inputs, outputs, and internal states of the physical computing system.[12]

Mathematical models[edit]

In the theory of computation, a diversity of mathematical models of computation has been developed. Typical mathematical models of computers are the following:

Giunti calls the models studied by computation theory computational systems, and he argues that all of them are mathematical dynamical systems with discrete time and discrete state space.[13]: ch.1  He maintains that a computational system is a complex object which consists of three parts. First, a mathematical dynamical system with discrete time and discrete state space; second, a computational setup , which is made up of a theoretical part , and a real part ; third, an interpretation , which links the dynamical system with the setup .[14]: pp.179–80 

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^ The study of non-computable statements is the field of hypercomputation.

References[edit]

  1. ^ Computation from the Free Merriam-Webster Dictionary
  • ^ "Computation: Definition and Synonyms from Answers.com". Answers.com. Archived from the original on 22 February 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2017.
  • ^ Couturat, Louis (1901). la Logique de Leibniz a'Après des Documents Inédits. Paris. ISBN 978-0343895099.
  • ^ Davis, Martin; Davis, Martin D. (2000). The Universal Computer. W. W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-04785-1.
  • ^ a b Davis, Martin (1982-01-01). Computability & Unsolvability. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-61471-7.
  • ^ Turing, A.M. (1937) [Delivered to the Society November 1936]. "On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem" (PDF). Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society. 2. Vol. 42. pp. 230–65. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-42.1.230.
  • ^ a b Davis, Martin; Davis, Martin D. (2000). The Universal Computer. W. W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-04785-1.
  • ^ Davis, Martin (2006). "Why there is no such discipline as hypercomputation". Applied Mathematics and Computation. 178 (1): 4–7. doi:10.1016/j.amc.2005.09.066.
  • ^ Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009), "Triviality Arguments against Functionalism", Philosophical Studies, 145 (2): 273–95, doi:10.1007/s11098-008-9231-3, S2CID 73619367
  • ^ Piccinini, Gualtiero (2015). Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 18. ISBN 9780199658855.
  • ^ Fodor, J. A. (1986), "The Mind-Body Problem", Scientific American, 244 (January 1986)
  • ^ Piccinini, Gualtiero (2015). Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 10. ISBN 9780199658855.
  • ^ Giunti, Marco (1997). Computation, Dynamics, and Cognition. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509009-3.
  • ^ Giunti, Marco (2017), "What is a Physical Realization of a Computational System?", Isonomia -- Epistemologica, 9: 177–92, ISSN 2037-4348

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Computation&oldid=1225163001"

    Categories: 
    Theoretical computer science
    Computability theory
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Wikipedia articles needing clarification from February 2022
     



    This page was last edited on 22 May 2024, at 18:59 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki