Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Biography  



1.1  Early years  





1.2  Career  







2 Awards  





3 Philosophy  



3.1  Givenness  





3.2  The saturated phenomenon  





3.3  "The Intentionality of Love"  







4 Publications  





5 See also  





6 References  





7 Sources  





8 Further reading  





9 External links  














Jean-Luc Marion






العربية
Català
Čeština
Deutsch
Español
فارسی
Français

Bahasa Indonesia
Italiano
עברית
Latina
مصرى
Nederlands

Polski
Português
Русский
Slovenščina
Svenska
Українська

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
Wikiquote
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Jean-Luc Marion
Born (1946-07-03) 3 July 1946 (age 77)
EducationLycée Condorcet
Alma materÉcole normale supérieure
Era20th-/21st-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
  • Phenomenology
  • Postmodernism
  • Catholic theology
  • Main interests

    Philosophical theology, Phenomenology, Descartes

    Notable ideas

    "As much reduction, as much givenness," saturated phenomenon, the intentionality of love, counter-experience

    Jean-Luc Marion (born 3 July 1946) is a French philosopher and Catholic theologian. He is a former student of Jacques Derrida whose work is informed by patristic and mystical theology, phenomenology, and modern philosophy.[1]

    Much of his academic work has dealt with Descartes and phenomenologists like Martin Heidegger and Edmund Husserl, but also religion. God Without Being, for example, is concerned predominantly with an analysis of idolatry, a theme strongly linked in Marion's work with love and the gift, which is a concept also explored at length by Derrida.

    Biography[edit]

    Early years[edit]

    Jean-Luc Marion at the Élysée Palace after his meeting with President Valéry Giscard d'Estaing on Thursday 7 September 1978.

    Marion was born in Meudon, Hauts-de-Seine, on 3 July 1946. He studied at the University of Nanterre (now the University Paris Ouest Nanterre La Défense) and the Sorbonne and then did graduate work in philosophy from the École normale supérieure in Paris from 1967 to 1971, where he was taught by Jacques Derrida, Louis Althusser and Gilles Deleuze.[2] At the same time, Marion's deep interest in theology was privately cultivated under the personal influence of theologians such as Louis Bouyer, Jean Daniélou, Henri de Lubac, and Hans Urs von Balthasar. From 1972 to 1980 he studied for his doctorate and worked as an assistant lecturer at the Sorbonne. After receiving his doctorate in 1980, he began teaching at the University of Poitiers.[2]

    Career[edit]

    From there he moved to become the Director of Philosophy at the University Paris X – Nanterre, and in 1991 also took up the role of professeur invité at the Institut Catholique de Paris.[3] In 1996 he became Director of Philosophy at the University of Paris IV (Sorbonne), where he taught until 2012.

    Marion became a visiting professor at the University of Chicago Divinity School in 1994. He was then appointed the John Nuveen Professor of the Philosophy of Religion and Theology there in 2004, a position he held until 2010.[4] That year, he was appointed the Andrew Thomas Greeley and Grace McNichols Greeley Professor of Catholic Studies at the Divinity School, a position that had been vacated by the retirement of theologian David Tracy.[5] He retired from Chicago in 2022. He continues to serve on the Editorial Advisory Panel of the journal Quaestio.

    On 6 November 2008, Marion was elected as an immortel by the Académie Française. Marion now occupies seat 4, an office previously held by Cardinal Lustiger.[6][7][8] In 2014, he delivered the Gifford LecturesonGivenness and Revelation at the University of Glasgow.[9]

    Awards[edit]

    His awards include:[6][10]

    Philosophy[edit]

    Marion's phenomenological work is set out in three volumes which together form a triptych[12]ortrilogy.[13] Réduction et donation: Etudes sur Husserl, Heidegger et la phénoménologie (1989) is an historical study of the phenomenological method followed by Husserl and Heidegger, with a view towards suggesting future directions for phenomenological research. The unexpected reaction that Réduction et donation provoked called for clarification and full development. This was addressed in Étant donné: Essai d'une phénoménologie de la donation (1997), a more conceptual work investigating phenomenological givenness, the saturated phenomenon and the gifted—a rethinking of the subject. Du surcroît (2001) provides an in-depth description of saturated phenomena.[14]

    Givenness[edit]

    Marion claims that he has attempted to "radically reduce the whole phenomenological project beginning with the primacy in it of givenness".[15] What he describes as his one and only theme is the givenness that is required before phenomena can show themselves in consciousness—"what shows itself first gives itself.[16] This is based on the argument that any and all attempts to lead phenomena back to immanence in consciousness, that is, to exercise the phenomenological reduction, necessarily results in showing that givenness is the "sole horizon of phenomena"[17]

    Marion radicalizes this argument in the formulation, "As much reduction, as much givenness",[18] and offers this as a new first principle of phenomenology, building on and challenging prior formulae of Husserl and Heidegger.[19] The formulation common to both, Marion argues, "So much appearance, so much Being", adopted from Johann Friedrich Herbart,[20] erroneously elevates appearing to the status of the "sole face of Being". In doing so, it leaves appearing itself undetermined, not subject to the reduction, and thus in a "typically metaphysical situation".[21]

    The Husserlian formulation, "To the things themselves!", is criticized on the basis that the things in question would remain what they are even without appearing to a subject—again circumventing the reduction or even without becoming phenomena. Appearing becomes merely a mode of access to objects, rendering the formulation inadequate as a first principle of phenomenology.[22] A third formulation, Husserl's "Principle of all Principles", states "that every primordial dator Intuition is a source of authority (Rechtsquelle) for knowledge, that whatever presents itself in 'intuition'...is simply to be accepted as it gives itself out to be, though only within the limits in which it then presents itself."[23] Marion argues that while the Principle of all Principles places givenness as phenomenality's criterion and achievement, givenness still remains uninterrogated.[24] Whereas it admits limits to intuition ("as it gives itself..., though only within the limits in which it presents itself"), "givenness alone is absolute, free and without condition"[25]

    Givenness then is not reducible except to itself, and so is freed from the limits of any other authority, including intuition; a reduced given is either given or not given. "As much reduction, as much givenness" states that givenness is what the reduction accomplishes, and any reduced given is reduced to givenness.[26] The more a phenomenon is reduced, the more it is given. Marion calls the formulation the last principle, equal to the first, that of the appearing itself.[27]

    Phenomenological reductions of Husserl, Heidegger and Marion[28]
      To whom are the things in question led back by the reduction? What is given by the reduction? How are the things in question given; what is the horizon? How far does the reduction go, what is excluded?
    First reduction – transcendental (Husserl) The intentional and constituting I Constituted objects Through regional ontologies. Through formal ontology, regional ontologies fall within the horizon of objectivity Excludes everything that does not let itself be led back to objectivity
    Second reduction – existential (Heidegger) Dasein: an intentionality broadened to Being-in-the-world and led back to its transcendence of beings through anxiety The different ways of Being; the "phenomenon of Being" According to Being as the original and ultimate phenomenon. According to the horizon of time Excludes that which does not have to be, especially the preliminary conditions of the phenomenon of Being, e.g. boredom, the claim
    Third reduction – to givenness (Marion) The interloqué: that which is called by the claim of the phenomenon[29] The gift itself; the gift of rendering oneself to or of eluding the claim of the call According to the horizon of the absolutely unconditional call and of the absolutely unconstrained response Absence of conditions and determinations of the claim. Gives all that can call and be called

    By describing the structures of phenomena from the basis of givenness, Marion claims to have succeeded in describing certain phenomena that previous metaphysical and phenomenological approaches either ignore or exclude—givens that show themselves but which a thinking that does not go back to the given is powerless to receive.[30] In all, three types of phenomena can be shown, according to the proportionality between what is given in intuition and what is intended:

    The saturated phenomenon[edit]

    Marion defines "saturated phenomena," which contradicts the Kantian claim that phenomena can only occur if they are congruent with the a priori knowledge upon which an observer's cognitive function is founded. For example, Kant would claim that the phenomenon "three years is a longer period of time than four years" cannot occur.[37]

    According to Marion, "saturated phenomena" (such as divine revelation) overwhelm the observer with their complete and perfect givenness, such that they are not shaped by the particulars of the observer's cognition at all. These phenomena may be conventionally impossible, and still occur because their givenness saturates the cognitive architecture innate to the observer.[38][39]

    "The Intentionality of Love"[edit]

    The fourth section of Marion's work Prolegomena to Charity is entitled "The Intentionality of Love" and primarily concerns intentionality and phenomenology. Influenced by (and dedicated to) the French philosopher Emmanuel Levinas, Marion explores the human idea of love and its lack of definition: "We live with love as if we knew what it was about. But as soon as we try to define it, or at least approach it with concepts, it draws away from us."[40] He begins by explaining the essence of consciousness and its "lived experiences." Paradoxically, the consciousness concerns itself with objects transcendent and exterior to itself, objects irreducible to consciousness, but can only comprehend its 'interpretation' of the object; the reality of the object arises from consciousness alone. Thus the problem with love is that to love another is to love one's own idea of another, or the "lived experiences" that arise in the consciousness from the "chance cause" of another: "I must, then, name this love my love, since it would not fascinate me as my idol if, first, it did not render to me, like an unseen mirror, the image of myself. Love, loved for itself, inevitably ends as self-love, in the phenomenological figure of self-idolatry."[40] Marion believes intentionality is the solution to this problem, and explores the difference between the I who intentionally sees objects and the me who is intentionally seen by a counter-consciousness, another, whether the me likes it or not. Marion defines another by its invisibility; one can see objects through intentionality, but in the invisibility of the other, one is seen. Marion explains this invisibility using the pupil: "Even for a gaze aiming objectively, the pupil remains a living refutation of objectivity, an irremediable denial of the object; here for the first time, in the very midst of the visible, there is nothing to see, except an invisible and untargetable void...my gaze, for the first time, sees an invisible gaze that sees it."[40] Love, then, when freed from intentionality, is the weight of this other's invisible gaze upon one's own, the cross of one's own gaze and the other's and the "unsubstitutability" of the other. Love is to "render oneself there in an unconditional surrender...no other gaze must respond to the ecstasy of this particular other exposed in his gaze." Perhaps in allusion to a theological argument, Marion concludes that this type of surrender "requires faith."[40]

    Publications[edit]

    See also[edit]

    References[edit]

    1. ^ Horner 2005.
  • ^ a b Horner 2005, p. 3.
  • ^ Horner 2005, p. 5.
  • ^ Horner, Robyn. Jean-Luc Marion: a Theo-Logical Introduction. Burlington: Ashgate, 2005.
  • ^ University of Chicago 2010.
  • ^ a b Académie française, 2008.
  • ^ L’Agence France-Presse 2008.
  • ^ a b Wein, Terren (October 8, 2020). "Pope Francis honors Prof. Jean-Luc Marion with one of world's top theology prizes". University of Chicago News.
  • ^ "The Glasgow Gifford Lectures". gla.ac.uk. University of Glasgow.
  • ^ University of Chicago Divinity School 2015.
  • ^ Merlo, Francesca (November 13, 2021). "Pope: Ratzinger Prize enriches human and spiritual heritage". Vatican News.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.ix.
  • ^ Marion 2002b, p.ix.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.ix-x.
  • ^ Marion 2002b, p.xxi.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.5.
  • ^ Robyn Horner, translator, in Marion 2002b, p.ix.
  • ^ Marion 1998, p.203; Marion 2002a, p.16; Marion 2002b, p.17-19; see Marion 2002b, p.x, note 4 for translator's note.
  • ^ Marion 1998, p.203; Marion 2002a, p.14-19; Marion 2002b, p.16-19.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.329, note 4.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.11.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.12.
  • ^ Husserl 1969, p.92.
  • ^ Marion 2002b, p.17.
  • ^ Husserl, Edmund. Die Idee der Phänomenologie, Husserliania II. pp. 61 and 50 respectively. Cited in Marion 1998, p.33 and Marion 2002b p.17-18.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, p.17.
  • ^ Marion 2002b, p.26.
  • ^ Marion 1998, pp.204–205.
  • ^ Marion 1998, pp. 200–202.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.3–4.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.222, 308.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.53–59.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.191–196.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.194, 226.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.222–225.
  • ^ Marion 2002a, pp.196–221, 225–247 and Marion 2002b.
  • ^ Kant, Immanuel (1999). Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-5216-5729-7.
  • ^ Mason, Brook (2014). "Saturated Phenomena, the Icon, and Revelation: A Critique of Marion's Account of Revelation and the "Redoubling" of Saturation" (PDF). Aporia. 24 (1): 25–37.
  • ^ Caputo 2007 p. 164.
  • ^ a b c d Marion 2002c
  • Sources[edit]

    Further reading[edit]

    External links[edit]


    Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Jean-Luc_Marion&oldid=1229108278"

    Categories: 
    1946 births
    Living people
    People from Meudon
    Lycée Condorcet alumni
    École Normale Supérieure alumni
    Paris Nanterre University alumni
    University of Chicago Divinity School faculty
    Academic staff of the University of Paris
    Academic staff of the University of Poitiers
    French historians of philosophy
    Catholic philosophers
    Postmodernists
    Phenomenologists
    Descartes scholars
    20th-century French philosophers
    20th-century French Catholic theologians
    21st-century French philosophers
    21st-century French Catholic theologians
    Members of the Académie Française
    Knights of the Legion of Honour
    Heidegger scholars
    French male writers
    Ratzinger Prize laureates
    Hidden categories: 
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Pages using infobox philosopher with unknown parameters
    Articles with hCards
    CS1 French-language sources (fr)
    Articles with FAST identifiers
    Articles with ISNI identifiers
    Articles with VIAF identifiers
    Articles with WorldCat Entities identifiers
    Articles with BIBSYS identifiers
    Articles with BNE identifiers
    Articles with BNF identifiers
    Articles with BNFdata identifiers
    Articles with CANTICN identifiers
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with ICCU identifiers
    Articles with J9U identifiers
    Articles with KBR identifiers
    Articles with LCCN identifiers
    Articles with Libris identifiers
    Articles with LNB identifiers
    Articles with NDL identifiers
    Articles with NKC identifiers
    Articles with NLA identifiers
    Articles with NLG identifiers
    Articles with NLK identifiers
    Articles with NSK identifiers
    Articles with NTA identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
    Articles with VcBA identifiers
    Articles with CINII identifiers
    Articles with DTBIO identifiers
    Articles with Trove identifiers
    Articles with SNAC-ID identifiers
    Articles with SUDOC identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 14 June 2024, at 22:32 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki