Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  



























Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Biography  



1.1  Chronology  



1.1.1  Date of birth  





1.1.2  Timeline relative to other Presocratics  







1.2  Anecdotes  



1.2.1  Archaeological discovery  





1.2.2  Visit to Athens  









2 On Nature  



2.1  Introduction  





2.2  The Way of Truth  





2.3  The Way of Opinion  







3 Legacy  





4 Notes  



4.1  Fragments  





4.2  Citations  







5 Bibliography  



5.1  Ancient testimony  



5.1.1  Life and doctrines  





5.1.2  Fragments  







5.2  Modern scholarship  







6 Further reading  





7 External links  














Parmenides






Afrikaans
العربية
Asturianu
Azərbaycanca

Беларуская
Български

Bosanski
Català
Čeština
Dansk
Davvisámegiella
Deutsch
Eesti
Ελληνικά
Español
Esperanto
Estremeñu
Euskara
فارسی
Føroyskt
Français
Gàidhlig
Galego

Հայերեն
ि
Hrvatski
Bahasa Indonesia
Íslenska
Italiano
עברית

Қазақша
Kurdî
Кыргызча
Latina
Latviešu
Lietuvių
Lingua Franca Nova
Magyar
Македонски
Malagasy

مصرى
مازِرونی
Mirandés
Nederlands

Norsk bokmål
Norsk nynorsk
Occitan
Oʻzbekcha / ўзбекча

پنجابی
Papiamentu
Piemontèis
Polski
Português
Română
Русский
سرائیکی
Scots
Shqip

Simple English
Slovenčina
Slovenščina
کوردی
Српски / srpski
Srpskohrvatski / српскохрватски
Suomi
Svenska
Татарча / tatarça

Türkçe
Українська
اردو
Tiếng Vit
Volapük
Winaray



 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
Wikiquote
Wikisource
 


















From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


Parmenides
Bust of Parmenides discovered at Velia, thought to have been partially modeled on a Metrodorus bust.
Bornc. late 6th century BC
Died
c. 5th century BC
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolEleatic school

Main interests

Ontology, poetry, cosmology

Notable ideas

Monism, truth/opinion distinction

Parmenides of Elea (/pɑːrˈmɛnɪdz ...ˈɛliə/; Greek: Παρμενίδης ὁ Ἐλεάτης; fl. late sixth or early fifth century BC) was a pre-Socratic Greek philosopher from EleainMagna Graecia.

Parmenides was born in the Greek colonyofElea, from a wealthy and illustrious family.[a] His dates are uncertain; according to doxographer Diogenes Laërtius, he flourished just before 500 BC,[b] which would put his year of birth near 540 BC, but in the dialogue Parmenides Plato has him visiting Athens at the age of 65, when Socrates was a young man, c. 450 BC,[c] which, if true, suggests a year of birth of c. 515 BC.[1] He is thought to have been in his prime (or "floruit") around 475 BC.[2]

The single known work by Parmenides is a poem whose original title is unknown but which is often referred to as On Nature. Only fragments of it survive. In his poem, Parmenides prescribes two views of reality. The first, the Way of "Aletheia" or truth, describes how all reality is one, change is impossible, and existence is timeless and uniform. The second view, the way of "Doxa", or opinion, describes the world of appearances, in which one's sensory faculties lead to conceptions which are false and deceitful.

Parmenides has been considered the founder of ontology and has, through his influence on Plato, influenced the whole history of Western philosophy.[3] He is also considered to be the founder of the Eleatic schoolofphilosophy, which also included Zeno of Elea and Melissus of Samos. Zeno's paradoxes of motion were developed to defend Parmenides' views. In contemporary philosophy, Parmenides' work has remained relevant in debates about the philosophy of time.

Biography[edit]

Parmenides was born in Elea (called Velia in Roman times), a city located in Magna Graecia. Diogenes Laertius says that his father was Pires, and that he belonged to a rich and noble family.[4] Laertius transmits two divergent sources regarding the teacher of the philosopher. One, dependent on Sotion, indicates that he was first a student of Xenophanes,[5] but did not follow him, and later became associated with a Pythagorean, Aminias, whom he preferred as his teacher. Another tradition, dependent on Theophrastus, indicates that he was a disciple of Anaximander.[6]

Chronology[edit]

Everything related to the chronology of Parmenides—the dates of his birth and death, and the period of his philosophical activity—is uncertain.[citation needed]

Date of birth[edit]

All conjectures regarding Parmenides' date of birth are based on two ancient sources. One comes from Apollodorus and is transmitted to us by Diogenes Laertius: this source marks the Olympiad 69th (between 504 BC and 500 BC) as the moment of maturity, placing his birth 40 years earlier (544 BC – 540 BC).[7] The other is Plato, in his dialogue Parmenides. There Plato composes a situation in which Parmenides, 65, and Zeno, 40, travel to Athens to attend the Panathenaic Games. On that occasion they meet Socrates, who was still very young according to the Platonic text.[8]

The inaccuracy of the dating from Apollodorus is well known, who chooses the date of a historical event to make it coincide with the maturity (the floruit) of a philosopher, a maturity that he invariably reached at forty years of age. He tries to always match the maturity of a philosopher with the birth of his alleged disciple. In this case Apollodorus, according to Burnet, based his date of the foundation of Elea (540 BC) to chronologically locate the maturity of Xenophanes and thus the birth of his supposed disciple, Parmenides.[9] Knowing this, Burnet and later classicists like Cornford, Raven, Guthrie, and Schofield preferred to base the calculations on the Platonic dialogue. According to the latter, the fact that Plato adds so much detail regarding ages in his text is a sign that he writes with chronological precision. Plato says that Socrates was very young, and this is interpreted to mean that he was less than twenty years old. We know the year of Socrates' death (399 BC) and his age—he was about seventy years old–making the date of his birth 469 BC. The Panathenaic games were held every four years, and of those held during Socrates' youth (454, 450, 446), the most likely is that of 450 BC, when Socrates was nineteen years old. Thus, if at this meeting Parmenides was about sixty-five years old, his birth occurred around 515 BC.[9][10][11][12][13][14][15]

However, neither Raven nor Schofield, who follows the former, finds a dating based on a late Platonic dialogue entirely satisfactory. Other scholars directly prefer not to use the Platonic testimony and propose other dates. According to a scholar of the Platonic dialogues, R. Hirzel, Conrado Eggers Lan indicates that the historical has no value for Plato.[16] The fact that the meeting between Socrates and Parmenides is mentioned in the dialogues Theaetetus (183e) and Sophist (217c) only indicates that it is referring to the same fictional event, and this is possible because both the Theaetetus and the Sophist are considered after the Parmenides. In Soph. 217c the dialectic procedure of Socrates is attributed to Parmenides, which would confirm that this is nothing more than a reference to the fictitious dramatic situation of the dialogue.[17] Eggers Lan proposes a correction of the traditional date of the foundation of Elea. Based on Herodotus I, 163–167, which indicates that the Phocians, after defeating the Carthaginians in naval battle, founded Elea, and adding the reference to Thucydides I, 13, where it is indicated that such a battle occurred in the time of Cambyses II, the foundation of Elea can be placed between 530 BC and 522 BC So Parmenides could not have been born before 530 BC or after 520 BC, given that it predates Empedocles.[18] This last dating procedure is not infallible either, because it has been questioned that the fact that links the passages of Herodotus and Thucydides is the same.[19] Nestor Luis Cordero also rejects the chronology based on the Platonic text, and the historical reality of the encounter, in favor of the traditional date of Apollodorus. He follows the traditional datum of the founding of Elea in 545 BC, pointing to it not only as terminus post quem, but as a possible date of Parmenides' birth, from which he concludes that his parents were part of the founding contingent of the city and that he was a contemporary of Heraclitus.[15] The evidence suggests that Parmenides could not have written much after the death of Heraclitus.[citation needed]

Timeline relative to other Presocratics[edit]

Beyond the speculations and inaccuracies about his date of birth, some specialists have turned their attention to certain passages of his work to specify the relationship of Parmenides with other thinkers. It was thought to find in his poem certain controversial allusions to the doctrine of Anaximenes and the Pythagoreans (fragment B 8, verse 24, and frag. B 4), and also against Heraclitus (frag .B 6, vv.8–9), while Empedocles and Anaxagoras frequently refer to Parmenides.[20]

The reference to Heraclitus has been debated. Bernays's thesis[21] that Parmenides attacks Heraclitus, to which Diels, Kranz, Gomperz, Burnet and others adhered, was discussed by Reinhardt,[22] whom Jaeger followed.[23]

Guthrie finds it surprising that Heraclitus would not have censured Parmenides if he had known him, as he did with Xenophanes and Pythagoras. His conclusion, however, does not arise from this consideration, but points out that, due to the importance of his thought, Parmenides splits the history of pre-Socratic philosophy in two; therefore his position with respect to other thinkers is easy to determine. From this point of view, the philosophy of Heraclitus seems to him pre-Parmenidean, while those of Empedocles, Anaxagoras and Democritus are post-Parmenidean.[11]

Anecdotes[edit]

Plutarch, Strabo and Diogenes—following the testimony of Speusippus—agree that Parmenides participated in the government of his city, organizing it and giving it a code of admirable laws.[24]

Detail of the pedestal found in Velia. Greek inscriptions were made only in capital letters, and without spaces. Read as follows: ΠΑ[ ]ΜΕΝΕΙΔΗΣ ΠΥΡΗΤΟΣ
ΟΥΛΙΑΔΗΣ ΦΥΣΙΚΟΣ

Archaeological discovery[edit]

In 1969, the plinth of a statue dated to the 1st century AD was excavated in Velia. On the plinth were four words: ΠΑ[Ρ]ΜΕΝΕΙΔΗΣ ΠΥΡΗΤΟΣ ΟΥΛΙΑΔΗΣ ΦΥΣΙΚΟΣ.[25] The first two clearly read "Parmenides, son of Pires." The fourth word φυσικός (fysikós, "physicist") was commonly used to designate philosophers who devoted themselves to the observation of nature. On the other hand, there is no agreement on the meaning of the third (οὐλιάδης, ouliadēs): it can simply mean "a native of Elea" (the name "Velia" is in Greek Οὐέλια),[26] or『belonging to the Οὐλιος』(Ulios), that is, to a medical school ( the patron of which was Apollo Ulius).[27] If this last hypothesis were true, then Parmenides would be, in addition to being a legislator, a doctor.[28] The hypothesis is reinforced by the ideas contained in fragment 18 of his poem, which contains anatomical and physiological observations.[29] However, other specialists believe that the only certainty we can extract from the discovery is that of the social importance of Parmenides in the life of his city, already indicated by the testimonies that indicate his activity as a legislator.[30]

Visit to Athens[edit]

Plato, in his dialogue Parmenides, relates that, accompanied by his disciple Zeno of Elea, Parmenides visited Athens when he was approximately sixty-five years old and that, on that occasion, Socrates, then a young man, conversed with him.[31] AthenaeusofNaucratis had noted that, although the ages make a dialogue between Parmenides and Socrates hardly possible, the fact that Parmenides has sustained arguments similar to those sustained in the Platonic dialogue is something that seems impossible.[32] Most modern classicists consider the visit to Athens and the meeting and conversation with Socrates to be fictitious. Allusions to this visit in other Platonic works are only references to the same fictitious dialogue and not to a historical fact.[33]

On Nature[edit]

Parmenides' sole work, which has only survived in fragments, is a poem in dactylic hexameter, later titled On Nature. Approximately 160 verses remain today from an original total that was probably near 800.[3] The poem was originally divided into three parts: an introductory proem that contains an allegorical narrative which explains the purpose of the work, a former section known as "The Way of Truth" (aletheia, ἀλήθεια), and a latter section known as "The Way of Appearance/Opinion" (doxa, δόξα). Despite the poem's fragmentary nature, the general plan of both the proem and the first part, "The Way of Truth" have been ascertained by modern scholars, thanks to large excerpts made by Sextus Empiricus[d] and Simplicius of Cilicia.[e][3] Unfortunately, the second part, "The Way of Opinion", which is supposed to have been much longer than the first, only survives in small fragments and prose paraphrases.[3]

Introduction[edit]

The introductory proem describes the narrator's journey to receive a revelation from an unnamed goddess on the nature of reality.[34] The remainder of the work is then presented as the spoken revelation of the goddess without any accompanying narrative.[34]

The narrative of the poet's journey includes a variety of allegorical symbols, such as a speeding chariot with glowing axles, horses, the House of Night, Gates of the paths of Night and Day, and maidens who are "the daughters of the Sun"[35] who escort the poet from the ordinary daytime world to a strange destination, outside our human paths.[36] The allegorical themes in the poem have attracted a variety of different interpretations, including comparisons to Homer and Hesiod, and attempts to relate the journey towards either illumination or darkness, but there is little scholarly consensus about any interpretation, and the surviving evidence from the poem itself, as well as any other literary use of allegory from the same time period, may be too sparse to ever determine any of the intended symbolism with certainty.[34]

The Way of Truth[edit]

In the Way of Truth, an estimated 90% of which has survived,[3] Parmenides distinguishes between the unity of nature and its variety, insisting in the Way of Truth upon the reality of its unity, which is therefore the object of knowledge, and upon the unreality of its variety, which is therefore the object, not of knowledge, but of opinion.[citation needed] This contrasts with the argument in the section called "the way of opinion", which discusses that which is illusory.[citation needed]

The Way of Opinion[edit]

In the significantly longer, but far worse preserved latter section of the poem, Way of Opinion, Parmenides propounds a theory of the world of seeming and its development, pointing out, however, that, in accordance with the principles already laid down, these cosmological speculations do not pretend to anything more than mere appearance. The structure of the cosmos is a fundamental binary principle that governs the manifestations of all the particulars: "the Aether fire of flame" (B 8.56), which is gentle, mild, soft, thin and clear, and self-identical, and the other is "ignorant night", body thick and heavy.[37][f] Cosmology originally comprised the greater part of his poem, explaining the world's origins and operations.[g] Some idea of the sphericity of the Earth also seems to have been known to Parmenides.[3][h]

Legacy[edit]

As the first of the Eleatics, Parmenides is generally credited with being the philosopher who first defined ontology as a separate discipline distinct from theology.[3] His most important pupil was Zeno, who appears alongside him in Plato's Parmenides where they debate dialectic with Socrates.[i] The pluralist theories of Empedocles and Anaxagoras and the atomist Leucippus, and Democritus have also been seen as a potential response to Parmenides' arguments and conclusions.[38] Parmenides is also mentioned in Plato's Sophist[j] and Theaetetus.[k] Later Hellenistic doxographers also considered Parmenides to have been a pupil of Xenophanes.[l] Eusebius of Caesarea, quoting Aristocles of Messene, says that Parmenides was part of a line of skeptical philosophy that culminated in Pyrrhonism for he, by the root, rejects the validity of perception through the senses whilst, at any rate, it is first through our five forms of senses that we become aware of things and then by faculty of reasoning.[m] Parmenides' proto-monismofthe One also influenced Plotinus and Neoplatonism.[citation needed]

Notes[edit]

Fragments[edit]

  1. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, (DK 28A1, 21)
  • ^ Diogenes Laërtius (DK 28A1, 23)
  • ^ Plato, Parmenides, 127a–128b (DK 28A5)
  • ^ Against the Mathematicians (DK 28B1)
  • ^ Commentary on Aristotle's Physics (DK 22B8)
  • ^ (DK 28B8.53–4)
  • ^ Stobaeus, i. 22. 1a
  • ^ DK 28B10
  • ^ (DK 28A5)
  • ^ Sophist, 241d
  • ^ Plato, Theaetetus, 183e
  • ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, i. 5; Sextus Empiricus, adv. Math. vii. 111; Clement of Alexandria, Stromata, i. 301; Diogenes Laërtius, ix. 21
  • ^ Eusebius, Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV, Chapter XVII
  • Citations[edit]

    1. ^ Curd 2004, pp. 3–8.
  • ^ Freeman 1946, p. 140.
  • ^ a b c d e f g Palmer 2020.
  • ^ (DK) A1 (Diogenes Laert, IX 21)
  • ^ The testimony of the link between Parmenides and Xenophanes goes back to Aristotle, Met. I 5, 986b (A 6) and from Plato, Sophist 242d (21 A 29)
  • ^ Tradition attesting Suidas (A 2).
  • ^ Diogenes Laertius, IX, 23 (DK testimony A 1).
  • ^ Plato, Parmenides 127 BC (A 5).
  • ^ a b Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, pp. 169ff.
  • ^ Cornford, Plato and Parmenides, p. 1.
  • ^ a b Guthrie, History of Greek Philosophy, II, p. 15ff.
  • ^ Raven, The Presocratic Philosophers, p. 370.
  • ^ Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers, p. 347.
  • ^ Plato, Parmenides (ed. Degrees), p. 33, note 13
  • ^ a b Cordero, Siendo se es, pp. 20-23
  • ^ R. Hirzel, Der Dialog, I, p. 185.
  • ^ Eggers Lan, The pre-Socratic philosophers, p. 410ff.
  • ^ Eggers Lan, The pre-Socratic philosophers, pp. 412ff.
  • ^ Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, p. 43, no. 106 of Torres Esbarranch.
  • ^ Raven, The Presocratic Philosophers, pp. 370s; 385s; 381.
  • ^ Bernays, Ges. Abh., 1, 62, n. 1.
  • ^ Reinhardt, Parmenides, p. 64.
  • ^ Jaeger, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers, p. 104.
  • ^ Strabo, Geography VI 1, 1 (A 12); Plutarch., Adv. Colot. 1126a (A 12); Speusippus, fr. 1, in Diog. L., IX, 23 (A 1).
  • ^ "IG XIV".
  • ^ Marcel Conche, Parménide : Le Poème: Fragments, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1996, p. 5 and note.
  • ^ P. Ebner, "Parmenide medico Ouliádes", in: Giornale di Metafisica 21 (1966), pp. 103-114
  • ^ Poema, intr. by Jorge Pérez de Tudela, p. 14
  • ^ Poema, comment by Jorge Pérez de Tudela, p. 230 and note ad. loc.
  • ^ N. L. Cordero, Being one is, p. 23.
  • ^ Plato, Parmenides 127 BC (A 11).
  • ^ Athenaeus, Deipnosophistae XI 505f (A 5)
  • ^ See Theaetetus 183e; Sophist 217c; see also «Introduction» to the dialogue Parménides by M.ª Isabel Santa Cruz, p. 11
  • ^ a b c Curd 2004, I.3.
  • ^ Kirk, Raven & Schofield 1983, p. 243.
  • ^ Furley 1973, pp. 1–15.
  • ^ Guthrie 1979, p. 61–62.
  • ^ Sedley 1998.
  • Bibliography[edit]

    Ancient testimony[edit]

    In the Diels–Kranz numbering for testimony and fragments of Pre-Socratic philosophy, Parmenides is catalogued as number 28. The most recent edition of this catalogue is:

    Diels, Hermann; Kranz, Walther (1957). Plamböck, Gert (ed.). Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (in Ancient Greek and German). Rowohlt. ISBN 5875607416. Retrieved 11 April 2022.

    Life and doctrines[edit]

  • A2. "Parmenides". Suda – via Suda Online.
  • A3.  Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). "Socrates, with predecessors and followers: Anaximenes" . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:2. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library. § 3.
  • A4. Iamblichus. Life of Pythagoras.
  • A5. Plato (1925). Parmenides. Plato in Twelve Volumes. Vol. 9. Translated by Harold N. Fowler. 127a.
  • A6. Aristotle. Metaphysics. 986b.
  • A7. Alexander of Aphrodisias. Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics. 984b.
  • A8. Simplicius. Commentary On Aristotle's Physics.
  • A9.  Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). "Others: Protagoras" . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 2:9. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
  • A10. Simplicius. Commentary On Aristotle's Physics.
  • A11. Eusebius. Chronicon Paschale.
  • A12. Strabo. Geographia. Book VI, §1.
  • Fragments[edit]

  • Simplicius (22 April 2014). Commentary On Aristotle Physics. Vol. 1.3-4. A&C Black. pp. 55–56. ISBN 978-1-4725-1531-5. Retrieved 13 April 2022.
  • Modern scholarship[edit]

  • Freeman, Kathleen (1946). The Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Great Britain in the City Of Oxford at the Alden Press: Oxford Basil Blackwell. p. 140.
  • Furley, D.J. (1973). Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy presented to Gregory Vlastos.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1979). A History of Greek Philosophy – The Presocratic tradition from Parmenides to Democritus. Cambridge University Press.
  • Kirk, G. S.; Raven, J. E.; Schofield, M. (1983). The presocratic philosophers : a critical history with a selection of texts (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 243. ISBN 978-0-521-27455-5. Retrieved 12 April 2022.
  • Nussbaum, Martha (1979). "Eleatic Conventionalism and Philoaus on the Conditions of Thought". Harvard Studies in Classical Philology. 83: 63–108. doi:10.2307/311096. JSTOR 311096.
  • Palmer, John (2020). "Parmenides". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Sedley, David (1998). "Parmenides". In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. London: Routledge. ISBN 9780415169165.
  • Further reading[edit]

  • Austin, Scott (15 July 2007). Parmenides and The History of Dialectic. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-53-7.
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005), Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing, ISBN 1-4120-4843-5
  • Barnes, Jonathan (1982). "Parmenides and the Objects of Inquiry". The Presocratic Philosophers. Routledge and Kegan Paul. pp. 155–175.
  • Cordero, Nestor-Luis (2004), By Being, It Is: The Thesis of Parmenides. Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-03-2
  • Cordero, Néstor-Luis (ed.), Parmenides, Venerable and Awesome (Plato, Theaetetus 183e) Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing 2011. Proceedings of the International Symposium (Buenos Aires, 2007), ISBN 978-1-930972-33-9
  • Coxon, but A. H. (2009), The Fragments of Parmenides: A Critical Text With Introduction and Translation, the Ancient Testimonia and a Commentary. Las Vegas, Parmenides Publishing (new edition of Coxon 1986), ISBN 978-1-930972-67-4
  • Curd, Patricia (2011), A Presocratics Reader: Selected Fragments and Testimonia, Hackett Publishing, ISBN 978-1603843058 (Second edition Indianapolis/Cambridge 2011)
  • Hermann, Arnold (2005), To Think Like God: Pythagoras and Parmenides-The Origins of Philosophy, Fully Annotated Edition, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-00-1
  • Hermann, Arnold (2010), Plato's Parmenides: Text, Translation & Introductory Essay, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-71-1
  • Mourelatos, Alexander P. D. (2008). The Route of Parmenides: A Study of Word, Image, and Argument in the Fragments. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-11-7 (First edition Yale University Press 1970)
  • Palmer, John. (2009). Parmenides and Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Extensive bibliography (up to 2004) by Nestor-Luis Cordero; and annotated bibliography by Raul Corazzon

    External links[edit]

  • Resources in other libraries
  • Resources in other libraries

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Parmenides&oldid=1217640318"

    Categories: 
    5th-century BC Greek philosophers
    5th-century BC poets
    510s BC births
    450s BC deaths
    Eleatic philosophers
    Ancient Greek epistemologists
    Lucanian Greeks
    Ancient Greek metaphysicians
    Ancient Greek physicists
    Ontologists
    Philosophers of Magna Graecia
    Ancient Greek philosophers of mind
    People from the Province of Salerno
    Hidden categories: 
    Harv and Sfn no-target errors
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    Pages using infobox philosopher with unknown parameters
    Articles with hCards
    Articles containing Ancient Greek (to 1453)-language text
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from December 2023
    Articles with unsourced statements from April 2022
    Articles with unsourced statements from September 2022
    CS1 foreign language sources (ISO 639-2)
    CS1 German-language sources (de)
    Wikipedia articles incorporating the template Lives of the Eminent Philosophers
    CS1: long volume value
    Commons category link is on Wikidata
    Articles with Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy links
    Articles with Internet Archive links
    Articles with LibriVox links
    Articles with FAST identifiers
    Articles with ISNI identifiers
    Articles with VIAF identifiers
    Articles with BIBSYS identifiers
    Articles with BNC identifiers
    Articles with BNE identifiers
    Articles with BNF identifiers
    Articles with BNFdata identifiers
    Articles with BNMM identifiers
    Articles with CANTICN identifiers
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with ICCU identifiers
    Articles with J9U identifiers
    Articles with KBR identifiers
    Articles with LCCN identifiers
    Articles with Libris identifiers
    Articles with NKC identifiers
    Articles with NLA identifiers
    Articles with NLG identifiers
    Articles with NLK identifiers
    Articles with NSK identifiers
    Articles with NTA identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
    Articles with PortugalA identifiers
    Articles with VcBA identifiers
    Articles with CINII identifiers
    Articles with ZBMATH identifiers
    Articles with DTBIO identifiers
    Articles with Trove identifiers
    Articles with SUDOC identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 7 April 2024, at 01:09 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki