Jump to content
 







Main menu
   


Navigation  



Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
 




Contribute  



Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
 








Search  

































Create account

Log in
 









Create account
 Log in
 




Pages for logged out editors learn more  



Contributions
Talk
 



















Contents

   



(Top)
 


1 Life  



1.1  Debate with C. S. Lewis  







2 Work  



2.1  On Wittgenstein  





2.2  Intention  





2.3  Ethics  





2.4  Brute and institutional facts  





2.5  First person  





2.6  Causality  







3 Views of her work  





4 Bibliography  



4.1  Books  





4.2  Select papers/book chapters  





4.3  Festschriften  







5 References  



5.1  Citations  





5.2  Sources  





5.3  Further reading  







6 External links  














G. E. M. Anscombe






العربية

Català
Čeština
Cymraeg
Deutsch
Eesti
Español
Euskara
فارسی
Français
Galego

Հայերեն
Hrvatski
Bahasa Indonesia
Íslenska
Italiano
עברית

Latina
Latviešu
Magyar

مصرى
Nederlands

Norsk bokmål
پښتو
Polski
Português
Русский
Slovenčina
Slovenščina
Suomi
Svenska
Türkçe
Українська

 

Edit links
 









Article
Talk
 

















Read
Edit
View history
 








Tools
   


Actions  



Read
Edit
View history
 




General  



What links here
Related changes
Upload file
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Get shortened URL
Download QR code
Wikidata item
 




Print/export  



Download as PDF
Printable version
 




In other projects  



Wikimedia Commons
Wikiquote
 
















Appearance
   

 






From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
 


G. E. M. Anscombe
Born

Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe


(1919-03-18)18 March 1919
Limerick, Ireland
Died5 January 2001(2001-01-05) (aged 81)
Cambridge, England
Other namesElizabeth Anscombe
Education
  • Newnham College, Cambridge
  • Notable work
    • Intention (1957)
  • "Modern Moral Philosophy" (1958)
  • Spouse

    (m. 1941)
    Era20th-century philosophy
    RegionWestern philosophy
    School
  • Analytical Thomism
  • InstitutionsUniversity of Oxford

    Main interests

    Notable ideas

  • Brute facts
  • Coining "consequentialism"
  • Direction of fit
  • Revival of virtue ethics
  • Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe FBA (/ˈænskəm/; 18 March 1919 – 5 January 2001), usually cited as G. E. M. AnscombeorElizabeth Anscombe, was a British[1] analytic philosopher. She wrote on the philosophy of mind, philosophy of action, philosophical logic, philosophy of language, and ethics. She was a prominent figure of analytical Thomism, a Fellow of Somerville College, Oxford, and a professor of philosophy at the University of Cambridge.

    Anscombe was a student of Ludwig Wittgenstein and became an authority on his work and edited and translated many books drawn from his writings, above all his Philosophical Investigations. Anscombe's 1958 article "Modern Moral Philosophy" introduced the term consequentialism into the language of analytic philosophy, and had a seminal influence on contemporary virtue ethics.[2] Her monograph Intention (1957) was described by Donald Davidson as "the most important treatment of action since Aristotle".[3][4] The continuing philosophical interest in the concepts of intention, action, and practical reasoning can be said to have taken its main impetus from this work.[citation needed]

    Life[edit]

    Anscombe was born to Gertrude Elizabeth (née Thomas) and Captain Allen Wells Anscombe, on 18 March 1919, in Limerick, Ireland, where her father had been stationed with the Royal Welch Fusiliers during the Irish War of Independence.[5] Both her mother and father were involved with education. Her mother was a headmistress and her father went on to head the science and engineering side at Dulwich College.[6]

    Anscombe attended Sydenham High School and then, in 1937, went on to read literae humaniores ('Greats') at St Hugh's College, Oxford. She was awarded a Second Class in her honour moderations in 1939 and (albeit it with reservations on the part of her Ancient History examiners[7]) a First in her degree finals in 1941.[6]

    While still at Sydenham High School, Anscombe converted to Catholicism. During her first year at St Hugh's, she was received into the church, and was a practising Catholic thereafter.[6]

    In 1941 she married Peter Geach. Like her, Geach was a Catholic convert who became a student of Wittgenstein and a distinguished academic philosopher. Together they had three sons and four daughters.[6]

    After graduating from Oxford, Anscombe was awarded a research fellowship for postgraduate studyatNewnham College, Cambridge, from 1942 to 1945.[6] Her purpose was to attend Ludwig Wittgenstein's lectures. Her interest in Wittgenstein's philosophy arose from reading the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus as an undergraduate. She claimed to have conceived the idea of studying with Wittgenstein as soon as she opened the book in Blackwell's and read section 5.53, "Identity of object I express by identity of sign, and not by using a sign for identity. Difference of objects I express by difference of signs." She became an enthusiastic student, feeling that Wittgenstein's therapeutic method helped to free her from philosophical difficulties in ways that her training in traditional systematic philosophy could not. As she wrote:

    For years, I would spend time, in cafés, for example, staring at objects saying to myself: 'I see a packet. But what do I really see? How can I say that I see here anything more than a yellow expanse?' ... I always hated phenomenalism and felt trapped by it. I couldn't see my way out of it but I didn't believe it. It was no good pointing to difficulties about it, things which Russell found wrong with it, for example. The strength, the central nerve of it remained alive and raged achingly. It was only in Wittgenstein's classes in 1944 that I saw the nerve being extracted, the central thought "I have got this, and I define 'yellow' (say) as this" being effectively attacked.

    — Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: The Collected Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe, Volume 2 (1981) pp. vii–x.

    After her fellowship at Cambridge ended, she was awarded a research fellowship at Somerville College, Oxford,[6] but during the academic year of 1946/47, she continued to travel to Cambridge once a week to attend tutorials with Wittgenstein that were devoted mainly to the philosophy of religion.[8] She became one of Wittgenstein's favourite students and one of his closest friends.[9][10] Wittgenstein affectionately addressed her by the pet name "old man" – she being (according to Ray Monk) "an exception to his general dislike of academic women".[9][10] His confidence in Anscombe's understanding of his perspective is shown by his choice of her as the translator of his Philosophical Investigations (for which purpose he arranged for her to spend some time in Vienna to improve her German[11][5]).

    Wittgenstein appointed Anscombe as one of his three literary executors and so she played a major role in translating and spreading his works.[12]

    Anscombe visited Wittgenstein many times after he left Cambridge in 1947, and Wittgenstein stayed at her house in Oxford for a period in 1950. She travelled to Cambridge in April 1951 to visit him on his deathbed. Wittgenstein named her, along with Rush Rhees and Georg Henrik von Wright, as his literary executor.[5][13] After his death in 1951 she was responsible for editing, translating, and publishing many of Wittgenstein's manuscripts and notebooks.[5][10]

    Anscombe did not avoid controversy. As an undergraduate in 1939 she had publicly criticised Britain's entry into the Second World War.[14] And, in 1956, while a research fellow, she unsuccessfully protested against Oxford granting an honorary degree to Harry S. Truman, whom she denounced as a mass murderer for his use of atomic bombs against Hiroshima and Nagasaki.[15][16][17] She would further publicise her position in a (sometimes erroneously dated[18]) pamphlet privately printed soon after Truman's nomination for the degree was approved. In the same she said she "should fear to go" to the Encaenia (the degree conferral ceremony) "in case God's patience suddenly ends."[19] She would also court controversy with some of her colleagues by defending the Catholic Church's opposition to contraception.[10] Later in life, she would be arrested protesting outside an abortion clinic, after abortion had been legalised in Great Britain.[16][20]

    Having remained at Somerville College since 1946, Anscombe was elected Professor of Philosophy at the University of Cambridge in 1970, where she served until her retirement in 1986. She was elected a fellow of the British Academy in 1967, and a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1979.[21]

    In her later years, Anscombe suffered from heart disease, and was nearly killed in a car crash in 1996. She never fully recovered and she spent her last years in the care of her family in Cambridge.[6] She died peacefully on 5 January 2001, aged 81, with her husband and four of their seven children at her hospital bedside just after praying the Sorrowful Mysteries of the rosary.[5] Anscombe's "last intentional act was kissing Peter Geach", her husband of sixty years.[22]

    She had not said where she was to be buried and the family chose what is now the Ascension Parish burial ground, as it was the nearest one to their home. There was some difficulty in getting a full-size plot, where she could be buried without being cremated first. This was not possible in the new part of the cemetery, so the site finally obtained – after negotiation with Ely diocesan authorities – was that of an old grave, corner-to-corner with the plot where Wittgenstein had been buried half a century before.[citation needed]

    Debate with C. S. Lewis[edit]

    As a young philosophy don, Anscombe acquired a reputation as a formidable debater. In 1948, she presented a paper at a meeting of Oxford's Socratic Club in which she disputed C. S. Lewis's argument that naturalism was self-refuting (found in the third chapter of the original publication of his book Miracles). Some associates of Lewis, primarily George Sayer and Derek Brewer, have remarked that Lewis lost the subsequent debate on her paper and that this loss was so humiliating that he abandoned theological argument and turned entirely to devotional writing and children's literature.[23] This is a claim disputed by Walter Hooper[24] and Anscombe's impression of the effect upon Lewis was somewhat different:

    The fact that Lewis rewrote that chapter, and rewrote it so that it now has those qualities [to address Anscombe's objections], shows his honesty and seriousness. The meeting of the Socratic Club at which I read my paper has been described by several of his friends as a horrible and shocking experience which upset him very much. Neither Dr Havard (who had Lewis and me to dinner a few weeks later) nor Professor Jack Bennet remembered any such feelings on Lewis' part ... My own recollection is that it was an occasion of sober discussion of certain quite definite criticisms, which Lewis' rethinking and rewriting showed he thought was accurate. I am inclined to construe the odd accounts of the matter by some of his friends – who seem not to have been interested in the actual arguments or the subject matter – as an interesting example of the phenomenon called "projection".

    — Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: The Collected Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe, Volume 2 (1981) p.x.

    As a result of the debate, Lewis substantially rewrote chapter 3 of Miracles for the 1960 paperback edition.[25]

    Work[edit]

    On Wittgenstein[edit]

    Some of Anscombe's most frequently cited works are translations, editions, and expositions of the work of her teacher Ludwig Wittgenstein, including an influential exegesis[26] of Wittgenstein's 1921 book, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. This brought to the fore the importance of Gottlob Frege for Wittgenstein's thought and, partly on that basis, attacked "positivist" interpretations of the work. She co-edited his posthumous second book, Philosophische Untersuchungen/Philosophical Investigations (1953) with Rush Rhees. Her English translation of the book appeared simultaneously and remains standard. She went on to edit or co-edit several volumes of selections from his notebooks, (co-)translating many important works like Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (1956) and Wittgenstein's "sustained treatment" of G. E. Moore's epistemology, On Certainty (1969).[27]

    In 1978, Anscombe was awarded the Austrian Cross of Honour for Science and Art, 1st class for her work on Wittgenstein.[28]

    Intention[edit]

    Her most important work is the monograph Intention (1957). Three volumes of collected papers were published in 1981: From Parmenides to Wittgenstein; Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind; and Ethics, Religion and Politics. Another collection, Human Life, Action and Ethics appeared posthumously in 2005.[11]

    The aim of Intention (1957) was to make plain the character of human action and will. Anscombe approaches the matter through the concept of intention, which, as she notes, has three modes of appearance in the English language:

    She is X'ing intentionally intentional action
    She is X'ing with the intention of doingY
    or ... She is X'ing to Y
    intention with which
    or further intention in acting
    She intends to Y
    or ... She has expressed the intention to do Y
    expression of intention for the future;
    (what Davidson later called a pure intending)

    She suggests that a true account must somehow connect these three uses of the concept, though later students of intention have sometimes denied this, and disputed some of the things she presupposes under the first and third headings. It is clear though that it is the second that is crucial to her main purpose, which is to comprehend the way in which human thought and understanding and conceptualisation relate to the "events in a man's history", or the goings on to which he is subject.

    Rather than attempt to define intentions in abstraction from actions, thus taking the third heading first, Anscombe begins with the concept of an intentional action. This soon connected with the second heading. She says that what is up with a human being is an intentional action if the question "Why", taken in a certain sense (and evidently conceived as addressed to him), has application.[29] An agent can answer the "why" question by giving a reason or purpose for her action. "To do Y" or "because I want to do Y" would be typical answers to this sort of "why?"; though they are not the only ones, they are crucial to the constitution of the phenomenon as a typical phenomenon of human life.[30] The agent's answer helps supply the descriptions under which the action is intentional. Anscombe was the first to clearly spell out that actions are intentional under some descriptions and not others. In her famous example, a man's action (which we might observe as consisting of moving an arm up and down while holding a handle) may be intentional under the description "pumping water" but not under other descriptions such as "contracting these muscles", "tapping out this rhythm", and so on. This approach to action influenced Donald Davidson's theory, despite the fact that Davidson went on to argue for a causal theory of action that Anscombe never accepted.[31][32]

    Intention (1957) is also the classic source for the idea that there is a difference in "direction of fit" between cognitive states like beliefs and conative states like desire. (This theme was later taken up and discussed by John Searle.)[33] Cognitive states describe the world and are causally derived from the facts or objects they depict. Conative states do not describe the world, but aim to bring something about in the world. Anscombe used the example of a shopping list to illustrate the difference.[34] The list can be a straightforward observational report of what is actually bought (thereby acting like a cognitive state), or it can function as a conative state such as a command or desire, dictating what the agent should buy. If the agent fails to buy what is listed, we do not say that the list is untrue or incorrect; we say that the mistake is in the action, not the desire. According to Anscombe, this difference in direction of fit is a major difference between speculative knowledge (theoretical, empirical knowledge) and practical knowledge (knowledge of actions and morals). Whereas "speculative knowledge" is "derived from the objects known", practical knowledge is – in a phrase Anscombe lifts from Aquinas – "the cause of what it understands".[35]

    Ethics[edit]

    Anscombe made great contributions to ethics as well as metaphysics. Her 1958 essay "Modern Moral Philosophy" is credited with having coined the term "consequentialism",[36] as well as with reviving interest in and study of virtue ethics in Western academic philosophy.[37][38]

    The Anscombe Bioethics Centre in Oxford is named after her, and conducts bioethical research in the Catholic tradition.[39]

    Brute and institutional facts[edit]

    Anscombe also introduced the idea of a set of facts being 'brute relative to' some fact. When a set of facts xyz stands in this relation to a fact A, they are a subset out of a range some subset among which holds if A holds. Thus if A is the fact that I have paid for something, the brute facts might be that I have handed him a cheque for a sum which he has named as the price for the goods, saying that this is the payment, or that I gave him some cash at the time that he gave me the goods. There tends, according to Anscombe, to be an institutional context which gives its point to the description 'A', but of which 'A' is not itself a description: that I have given someone a shilling is not a description of the institution of money or of the currency of the country. According to her, no brute facts xyz can generally be said to entail the fact A relative to which they are 'brute' except with the proviso "under normal circumstances", for "one cannot mention all the things that were not the case, which would have made a difference if they had been."[40] A set of facts xyz ... may be brute relative to a fact A which itself is one of a set of facts ABC ... which is brute relative to some further fact W. Thus Anscombe's account is not of a distinct class of facts, to be distinguished from another class, 'institutional facts': the essential relation is that of a set of facts being 'brute relative to' some fact. Following Anscombe, John Searle derived another conception of 'brute facts' as non-mental facts to play the foundational role and generate similar hierarchies in his philosophical account of speech acts and institutional reality.[41]

    First person[edit]

    Her paper "The First Person"[31] buttressed remarks by Wittgenstein (in his Lectures on "Private Experience"[42]) arguing for the now-notorious conclusion that the first-person pronoun, "I", does not refer to anything (not, e.g., to the speaker) because of its immunity from reference failure. Having shown by counter-example that 'I' does not refer to the body, Anscombe objected to the implied Cartesianism of its referring at all. Few people accept the conclusion – though the position was later adopted in a more radical form by David Lewis – but the paper was an important contribution to work on indexicals and self-consciousness that has been carried on by philosophers as varied as John Perry, Peter Strawson, David Kaplan, Gareth Evans, John McDowell, and Sebastian Rödl.[43]

    Causality[edit]

    In her article, "Causality and Determination",[44] Anscombe defends two main ideas: that causal relations are perceivable, and that causation does not require a necessary connection and a universal generalization linking cause and effect. Regarding her idea that causal relations are perceivable, she believes that we perceive the causal relations between objects and events.

    In defending her idea that causal relations are perceivable, Anscombe poses a question "How did we come by our primary knowledge of causality?".[44] She proposes two answers to this question:

    1. By "learning to speak, we learned the linguistic representation and application of a host of causal concepts"[44]
    2. By observing that some action(s) caused a certain event

    In proposing her first answer, that by "learning to speak, we learned the linguistic representation and application of a host of causal concepts", Anscombe thinks that by learning to speak we already have a linguistic representation of certain causal concepts and she gives an example of transitive verbs, such as scrape, push, carry, knock over.

    Example: I knocked over a vase of flowers.

    In proposing her second answer, that by observing some actions we can see causation, Anscombe thinks that we cannot ignore the fact that certain actions, which produced a certain event are possible to observe.

    Example: a cat spilled milk.

    The second idea that Anscombe defends in the article "Causality and Determination"[44] is that causation requires neither a necessary connection nor a universal generalization linking cause and effect.

    Anscombe states that it is assumed that causality is some kind of necessary connection.[44]

    Views of her work[edit]

    The philosopher Candace Vogler says that Anscombe's "strength" is that "'when she is writing for [a] Catholic audience, she presumes they share certain fundamental beliefs,' but she is equally willing to write for people who do not share her assumptions."[45] In 2010, philosopher Roger Scruton wrote that Anscombe was "perhaps the last great philosopher writing in English".[46] Mary Warnock described her as "the undoubted giant among women philosophers"[47] while John Haldane said she "certainly has a good claim to be the greatest woman philosopher of whom we know".[37]

    Bibliography[edit]

    Books[edit]

    Select papers/book chapters[edit]

    Festschriften[edit]

    References[edit]

    Citations[edit]

    1. ^ Boxer, Sarah (13 January 2001). "G. E. M. Anscombe, 81, British Philosopher". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 17 June 2019.
  • ^ "Ninety-four pages & then some: Roger Teichmann interviewed by Richard Marshall". 3:16. Retrieved 14 June 2021. Anscombe's paper was rightly credited with having helped start up the renewed interest in Aristotelian ethics, an interest which produced what is now often called 'virtue ethics'.
  • ^ Wiseman, Rachael (1 January 2015). "Anscombe's Intention". Jurisprudence. 6 (1): 182–193. doi:10.5235/20403313.6.l.182 (inactive 31 January 2024). ISSN 2040-3313.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024 (link)
  • ^ Stoutland, Frederick (2011). "Introduction: Anscombe's Intention in Context". Essays on Anscombe's Intention. Anton Ford, Jennifer Hornsby, Frederick Stoutland. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. pp. 1–22. doi:10.4159/harvard.9780674060913.intro. ISBN 978-0-674-06091-3. OCLC 754715004.
  • ^ a b c d e Teichman, Jenny (2003). Thompson, F.M.L (ed.). Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe, 1919–2001 (PDF). British Academy. doi:10.5871/bacad/9780197262788.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-175421-0. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help)
  • ^ a b c d e f g Teichman, Jenny (2017). "Anscombe, (Gertrude) Elizabeth Margaret (1919–2001), philosopher | Oxford Dictionary of National Biography". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/75032. Retrieved 17 June 2019. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
  • ^ Teichmann, Roger (2008). "Introduction". The Philosophy of Elizabeth Anscombe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-153845-2. OCLC 269285454. The philosophy examiners wanted to give her a First ... but the ancient history examiners would agree to this only on condition that she showed a minimum knowledge of their subject in a viva voce (oral) examination. Anscombe's performance ... was less than spectacular... To the last two questions she answered 'No', these being 'Can you give us the name of a Roman provincial governor?' and (in some desperation) 'Is there any fact about the period you are supposed to have studied which you would like to tell us?' The examiners cannot have been well pleased, but somehow or other ended up being persuaded by the philosophers ... As Michael Dummett writes in his obituary ... 'For the [ancient historians] to have yielded, her philosophy papers must have been astonishing'.
  • ^ Drury, M. O'C. (Maurice O'Connor) (21 September 2017). The selected writings of Maurice O'Connor Drury : on Wittgenstein, philosophy, religion and psychiatry. Hayes, John (Professor of Philosophy). London. pp. 407–409. ISBN 978-1-4742-5636-0. OCLC 946967786.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • ^ a b Monk, Ray. (1990). Ludwig Wittgenstein : the duty of genius (1st American ed.). New York: Free Press. pp. 497–498. ISBN 0-02-921670-2. OCLC 21560991.
  • ^ a b c d Driver, Julia (2018), "Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 19 June 2019
  • ^ a b The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Kuusela, Oskari., McGinn, Marie. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2011. pp. 715 (fn.2). ISBN 978-0-19-928750-5. OCLC 764568769.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  • ^ Michael L. Coulter; Richard S. Myers; Joseph A. Varacalli (2012). Encyclopedia of Catholic Social Thought, Social Science, and Social Policy Supplement. Vol. 3. Scarecrow Press. p. 6. ISBN 9780810882751.
  • ^ Macolm, Norman (1967). Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press. p. 97.
  • ^ "Professor G E M Anscombe". The Daily Telegraph. 6 January 2001. ISSN 0307-1235. Archived from the original on 12 January 2022. Retrieved 19 June 2019. In the autumn of 1939, while still an undergraduate, she and a friend wrote a pamphlet entitled The Justice of the Present War Examined. In this, Elizabeth Anscombe argued that while Britain was certainly fighting against an unjust cause, it was not fighting for a just one. ... Subsequently, the Catholic Archbishop of Birmingham told the two students to withdraw the pamphlet because they had described it as Catholic without getting a Church licence.
  • ^ MEYERS, DIANA TIETJENS (2008). "Anscombe, Elizabeth". The Oxford encyclopedia of women in world history. Smith, Bonnie G. (ed.). Oxford [England]: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-514890-9. OCLC 167505633. Anscombe ... opposed Britain's entry into World War II on the grounds that fighting the war would certainly involve killing non-combatants. When Oxford decided to award the U.S. president Harry Truman an honorary degree in 1956, Anscombe protested vigorously, arguing that the atomic bombing of innocent civilians at Hiroshima and Nagasaki disqualified him for such an honour.
  • ^ a b "Elizabeth Anscombe // de Nicola Center for Ethics and Culture // University of Notre Dame". ethicscenter.nd.edu. Retrieved 6 May 2019. Anscombe ... was a vigorous opponent of the use of nuclear weapons and led a protest of Oxford's awarding a degree to President Harry Truman on the grounds that a mass-murderer should not be so honoured. She was also a fierce opponent of abortion; on one occasion late in her life, she had to be dragged bodily by police away from a sit-in at an abortion clinic.
  • ^ Wiseman, Rachael (2016). "The Intended and Unintended Consequences of Intention" (PDF). American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. 90 (2): 207–227. doi:10.5840/acpq201622982. Retrieved 17 June 2019. On 1st May 1956, Oxford University's Convocation ...considered nominations for honorary degrees ... One of the nominations was Harry S. Truman ... Anscombe ..."caused a small stir" ... by arguing that the nomination should be rejected on the grounds that Truman was guilty of mass murder ... Anscombe's speech did not persuade ...The House was asked to indicate its attitude toward the nomination, and showed overwhelming support. ... On 20th June, Truman was awarded his honorary degree
  • ^ Gormally, L. – Kietzmann, C. – Torralba, J. M., Bibliography of Works by G.E.M. Anscombe, Seventh Version – June 2012 The date in CP is "1957" and there is no date in the original pamphlet. However, according to the facts it must have been published in 1956. The Honorary Degree was conferred on June 20th. 1956 and the Bodleian stamp of the pamphlet is "11 July 1956". See Torralba, J. M., Acción intencional y razonamiento práctico según G.E.M. Anscombe, Pamplona: Eunsa, 2005, pp. 58-61.
  • ^ "G. E. M. Anscombe "Mr. Truman's Degree"". 1956. Retrieved 17 June 2019.
  • ^ "Rare Pics Surface of Elizabeth Anscombe Arrested for Blocking Abortion Clinic". ChurchPOP. 18 October 2016. Retrieved 13 June 2019.
  • ^ "Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter A" (PDF). American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 19 April 2011.
  • ^ O'Grady, J. 2001. 'Obituary: Elizabeth Anscombe', The Guardian 11 January 2001, Guardian Leader Pages, p. 26. It is quoted in Jones, David Albert, "Portrait of a Catholic Philosopher," The Pastoral Review, May 2006. [1] Archived 31 March 2022 at the Wayback Machine
  • ^ "Frequently Asked Questions about C.S. Lewis". Biblical Discernment Ministries. 1999. Archived from the original on 24 October 2005. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • ^ "Truth about Anscombe v C S Lewis". The Telegraph. 11 January 2001. Archived from the original on 24 March 2021. Retrieved 24 March 2021. when writing my C. S. Lewis: a Companion and Guide (1996). Lewis told me in 1963 that he thought he won the debate with Anscombe at the Socratic Club in 1948. However, he accepted that he had been unclear and revised Chapter III of the book. Ironically, many philosophers disagree with Anscombe's argument, and maintain that the original chapter was philosophically sound, and that Lewis did not need to rewrite it. It is also not true that Lewis "never again wrote straightforward polemics for Christianity". In 1952, he revised his BBC wartime broadcasts as Mere Christianity. That book has probably caused more people to accept the faith than any other philosophical tome of the last century. Lewis was a man of such titanic imagination that he didn't need to go over and over the same ideas. It was not fear of Anscombe or anyone else that caused him to write the seven incomparable Chronicles of Narnia in the 1950s. Three theological works followed them.
  • ^ Smilde, Arend (6 December 2017). "What Lewis really did to Miracles A philosophical layman's attempt to understand the Anscombe affair". Journal of Inklings Studies. 1 (2): 9–24. doi:10.3366/ink.2011.1.2.3.
  • ^ Anscombe, G. E. M. (1959). An Introduction to Wittgenstein's Tractatus. London: Hutchinson.
  • ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1969). On Certainty. Oxford: BasilBlackwell.
  • ^ "Reply to a Parliamentary Question" (PDF) (in German). Vienna. p. 521. Retrieved 21 October 2012.
  • ^ Anscombe 1957, sec. 5–8.
  • ^ Anscombe 1957, sec. 18–21.
  • ^ a b Anscombe, G. E. M. (1981). Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind (collected papers vol 2). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. pp. 21–36. ISBN 0-631-12932-4.
  • ^ Anscombe 1957.
  • ^ Searle, John R. (1983). Intentionality, an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-22895-6. OCLC 9196773.
  • ^ See Anscombe 1957, sec. 32.
  • ^ See Anscombe 1957, sec. 48.
  • ^ Seidel, Christian (2019). Consequentialism: new directions, new problems. Oxford moral theory. New York (N.Y.): Oxford university press. pp. 2–3. ISBN 978-0-19-027011-7.
  • ^ a b Haldane, John (2000). "In Memoriam: G. E. M. Anscombe (1919–2001)" (PDF). The Review of Metaphysics. 53 (4): 1019–1021. ISSN 0034-6632.
  • ^ "Introduction". Virtue ethics. Crisp, Roger, Slote, Michael. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1997. pp. 3. ISBN 0-19-875189-3. OCLC 37028589.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  • ^ "Home". bioethics.org.uk.
  • ^ Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). "On Brute Facts". Analysis. 18 (3): 69–72. doi:10.2307/3326788. JSTOR 3326788.
  • ^ Searle, John (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. London: Allen Lane The Penguin Press. pp. 120–121. ISBN 0-14-023590-6.
  • ^ Wittgenstein, Lugwig (1993). "Notes for Lectures on "Private Experience" and "Sense Data"". In Klagge, J.; Nordmann, A. (eds.). Philosophical Occasions. Indianapolis: Hackett. p. 228.
  • ^ "Into the Coast: Sebastian Rödl". 10 January 2019.
  • ^ a b c d e Anscombe, G.E.M. "Causality and Determination". Metaphysics, edited by Jaewon Kim, Daniel Z. Korman and Ernest Sosa, Wiley-Blackwell, 2012, pp. 386-396.
  • ^ Oppenheimer, Mark (8 January 2011). "Renaissance for Outspoken Catholic Philosopher". The New York Times. p. A14. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • ^ Scruton, Roger (2010). "Wine and Philosophy". Decanter. Vol. 35. pp. 57–59. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • ^ Warnock, Mary, ed. (1996). Women Philosophers. London: J.M.Dent & Sons Ltd. ISBN 0-460-87738-0. OCLC 34407377.
  • Sources[edit]

    Further reading[edit]

  •  ———  (1981). "On Transubstantiation". Ethics, Religion and Politics. The Collected Philosophical Papers of G. E. M. Anscombe. Vol. 3. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 107–112. ISBN 978-0-631-12942-4 – via Second Spring.
  •  ———  (1993) [rev. ed. first published 1975]. "Contraception and Chastity [rev. ed.]" (PDF). In Smith, Janet E. (ed.). Why Humanae Vitae Was Right: A Reader. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. Archived from the original (PDF) on 9 November 2017. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Doyle, Bob. "G. E. M. Anscombe". The Information Philosopher. Cambridge, Massachusetts. Retrieved 10 November 2017.
  • Driver, Julia (2014). "Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Gormally, Luke (2011). "G E M Anscombe (1919–2001)" (PDF). Oxford: Anscombe Bioethics Centre. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 July 2021. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • O'Grady, Jane (11 January 2011). "Elizabeth Anscombe". The Guardian. London. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • "Portrait of a Catholic Philosopher". Oxford: Anscombe Bioethics Centre. Archived from the original on 21 January 2017. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Mac Cumhaill, Clare; Wiseman, Rachael (2022). Metaphysical animals : how four women brought philosophy back to life. London. ISBN 978-0-385-54570-9. OCLC 1289274891.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  • "Professor G E M Anscombe". The Telegraph. London. 22 November 2001. Archived from the original on 7 April 2008. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Richter, Duncan. "G. E. M. Anscombe (1919–2001)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Rutler, George W. (2004). "G. E. M. Anscombe". Cloud of Witnesses. Crisis. Vol. 22, no. 8. Washington: Morley Publishing Group. Archived from the original on 14 August 2007. Retrieved 9 November 2017.
  • Teichman, Jenny (2003). "Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe, 1919–2001". In Thompson, F. M. L. (ed.). Biographical Memoirs of Fellows. Volume 1. Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol. 115. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.5871/bacad/9780197262788.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-726278-8.
  • Torralba, José M. (2014). "G.E.M. Anscombe Bibliography". Pamplona, Spain: University of Navarra. Retrieved 10 November 2017.
  • External links[edit]

  • icon Catholicism
  • Philosophy

  • Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=G._E._M._Anscombe&oldid=1228872003"

    Categories: 
    1919 births
    2001 deaths
    20th-century British philosophers
    Action theorists
    Alumni of Newnham College, Cambridge
    Alumni of St Hugh's College, Oxford
    Analytic philosophers
    Anti-contraception activists
    British Roman Catholics
    Cambridge University Moral Sciences Club
    Christian ethicists
    Converts to Roman Catholicism
    Fellows of Newnham College, Cambridge
    Fellows of Somerville College, Oxford
    Fellows of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences
    Fellows of the British Academy
    People educated at Sydenham High School
    People from Sydenham, London
    British philosophers of language
    British philosophers of mind
    Presidents of the Aristotelian Society
    Recipients of the Austrian Cross of Honour for Science and Art, 1st class
    Catholic philosophers
    Analytical Thomists
    Roman Catholic writers
    Virtue ethicists
    Wittgensteinian philosophers
    British women philosophers
    Bertrand Russell Professors of Philosophy
    Hidden categories: 
    CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024
    CS1 errors: periodical ignored
    Wikipedia articles incorporating a citation from the ODNB
    CS1 maint: location missing publisher
    CS1 maint: others
    Webarchive template wayback links
    CS1 German-language sources (de)
    Articles with short description
    Short description is different from Wikidata
    EngvarB from August 2014
    Use dmy dates from August 2014
    Articles with hCards
    No local image but image on Wikidata
    Pages using sidebar with the child parameter
    All articles with unsourced statements
    Articles with unsourced statements from June 2020
    Articles with unsourced statements from October 2021
    Articles using small message boxes
    Incomplete lists from July 2016
    Articles containing Spanish-language text
    Pages using Sister project links with hidden wikidata
    Articles with FAST identifiers
    Articles with ISNI identifiers
    Articles with VIAF identifiers
    Articles with WorldCat Entities identifiers
    Articles with BIBSYS identifiers
    Articles with BNE identifiers
    Articles with BNF identifiers
    Articles with BNFdata identifiers
    Articles with BNMM identifiers
    Articles with CANTICN identifiers
    Articles with GND identifiers
    Articles with ICCU identifiers
    Articles with J9U identifiers
    Articles with KBR identifiers
    Articles with LCCN identifiers
    Articles with Libris identifiers
    Articles with LNB identifiers
    Articles with NDL identifiers
    Articles with NKC identifiers
    Articles with NLA identifiers
    Articles with NLG identifiers
    Articles with NLK identifiers
    Articles with NSK identifiers
    Articles with NTA identifiers
    Articles with PLWABN identifiers
    Articles with PortugalA identifiers
    Articles with CINII identifiers
    Articles with MGP identifiers
    Articles with ZBMATH identifiers
    Articles with DTBIO identifiers
    Articles with Trove identifiers
    Articles with SUDOC identifiers
     



    This page was last edited on 13 June 2024, at 17:40 (UTC).

    Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.



    Privacy policy

    About Wikipedia

    Disclaimers

    Contact Wikipedia

    Code of Conduct

    Developers

    Statistics

    Cookie statement

    Mobile view



    Wikimedia Foundation
    Powered by MediaWiki